Plagiarism
Agnes:
Hi Robin.
Robin:
Hi Agnes. We have come again to talk about whatever topics we end up talking
about! We can’t predict that very well. But we’ve decided on an introductory
question that I’m going to ask you, which is what’s so good about plagiarism?
I hear you’re a big fan!
Agnes:
[Laughs] Uh, no. I’m not. What I am is somebody who is skeptical that the
norms against plagiarism grip anything real in the whole bedrock, by contrast
with some of our other norms which I think are tracking like genuine value.
Robin:
Well I’m sure you are aware of the usual reasons academics would give against
plagiarism. So do you want to summarize them to criticize them? Or should I?
Or…
Agnes:
Well, maybe one thing I’ll say is, it is striking to note the place of these
norms within academia. Like if you want to debate stuff with academics, right,
you could debate almost any topic: You could ask, you know, is it okay to kill
babies? Or, you know, maybe torture is sometimes okay. That would be like a
topic where you can get people to take both sides. And interestingly, I found
the one thing all academics will agree on is how terrible plagiarism is. It’s
our kind of like moral code. So I agree with you, it plays in especially…
Robin:
Okay, but that’s not what the argument for it is.
Agnes:
No. That’s not the argument for it—
Robin:
In essence, it’s—
Agnes:
I’m just agreeing that they cherish it. So now you give me the argument.
Robin:
So for example, I’ve considered being a columnist or a pundit. I look at what
pundits write and I notice that they don’t try to situate what they say in the
context of other things other people said. And so they often repeat things.
The columnist today might say the same thing as a columnist did 70 years ago
in some other city. And they’re fine with that, and they don’t even care to
notice. Right? It’s just about having something compelling for their
audience.
And that academia has this norm of doing things to accumulate.
We’re not just trying to say things that our audience might like, we’re trying
to build this edifice of all these things we’ve learned. And in order to do
that, what we need is for each person to say a new thing and try to convince
us it is a new thing, and therefore to put it in context of old things that
are nearby and to explain how their thing is new. And if we expect that people
consistently do that, then we can try to believe more that we are making new
things, and therefore we’re accumulating and building something that lasts and
becomes bigger rather than just cycling around in the space of the same topics
and the same things anybody’s ever said.
Agnes:
Yeah, so I agree with you that there are norms as to how you should conduct
research in academia. And I agree with you that quite often citations are
useful for the reader. But I think the norms against plagiarism extend far
beyond that. And so one thing you could do is you could compare somebody who
writes a paper, but he just doesn’t do a good job reading the literature—I
often find this in my own field, someone will not have read like half of the
important papers, right?
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
And people will be annoyed by that. But they will not react similarly to
someone who just copies an idea—that occasions outrage as opposed to merely a
kind of shoddy job with respect to these research norms. So I think that
plagiarism— The norms about plagiarism are not, in the first instance,
designed to further intellectual inquiry, they are more about an honor. Right?
So people want credit.
And academics in particular don’t—unlike
pundits—don’t make a lot of money from their ideas, right? So they have to
make something else from their ideas. And I mean, they have a salary, right,
but for many academics that doesn’t feel sufficient to them. They feel—
academics feel underpaid. And so they want to be paid in the currency of
honor. And you know, being cited is part of how they get paid in that
currency. It’s also part of how they get promoted—it’s like there’s a whole
system around that. So I tend to think the plagiarism norms function more
directly as part of that honor system than issues of research.
Robin:
Well, can’t we just call it a credit system?
Agnes:
Yes, it’s credit. Right. But the reason you want the credit is either honor or
you want to parlay the honor into a higher salary or something.
Robin:
But in a great many institutions in society, credit is important. That is, we
want to allocate resources according to some sort of outcomes, and a key issue
is credit for them. So like in a business, if there was a new product and it’s
successful, then we want to know, Well, who was responsible for introducing
this new product, and whoever can successfully correctly take the credit
should correctly be given credit in that business, right?
Agnes:
Why is that important that they’d be given the credit because they came up
with it?
Robin:
Because it was work. So but you know, so we can think about accounting systems
in general: Like in most companies, you have cost accounting primarily, you
primarily see the cost of buildings and the cost of materials and people’s
time and things like that. And you’re trying to make sure you know where all
the costs were and when.
Then you know, not just so you can help minimize
costs by rearranging it, but also to look out for cheating—for people
stealing, right? Accounting is to prevent theft, in part. But in most
businesses they actually do a relatively poor job of giving accounting for
work to develop ideas, and like a new product.
And so you might hope that
there was a better accounting system for the work that goes to create a good
idea, because then you— because you might fear that somebody who can get away
with it—and often managers can simply take credit for the good ideas that
happen and disavow credit for the bad ideas, and then, you know, arbitrarily
look good according to this accounting system, but not actually be good,
right? The more that the accounting system fails to credit or account for
things that are actually there, the less it’s useful as a guide to decision.
Agnes:
I mean, so if I were an economist I might say, Well, what seems to me to
matter would be like, do you have sufficient incentives for people to produce
these ideas? And maybe you need to give them this credit, right, in order to
incentivize the production of the ideas?
Robin:
Indeed.
Agnes:
One thing is like, if what you’re getting is a lot of idea production but
other people taking credit for it, apparently you don’t need those incentives,
right? Apparently people are still producing ideas!
Robin:
But they just got too little production.
Agnes:
Right, so you can get more production if you give more credit.
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
So I am not— I think that’s right. So it may well be that at least in certain
contexts, having plagiarizing norms is— anti-plagiarism norms— is sort of an
efficient way of organizing a certain kind of activity. So I think in
particular, for instance papers, right? Students have to write papers, and
then they get graded on those papers, right? And if they plagiarized and wrote
someone else’s paper, that would be cheating, right? And then that kind of
screws up your whole system.
Robin:
You can’t evaluate them, because they didn’t—
Agnes:
Right. And so— and I think— So I think that you could say that it’s sort of
problematic that way. That would be analogous to how— Suppose you had a
take-home exam and they were only supposed to take one day for it, but someone
found a way to take two days for it, right?
Robin:
Right. Got it early, perhaps.
Agnes:
So that’s like— That’s cheating in the sense that you sort of set up—you
create a set of rules, and the set of rules are designed so that they give
people the proper incentives, right, to get your result. And then some people
are sort of cheating.
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
And so if you want to say insofar as plagiarism is cheating—well, you know,
just as you taking an extra day on the test would be cheating, right?—then
sure, it might be wrong in that way if you happen to arbitrarily set up your
system with this rule, and when people break the rule it's a problem. But
that’s why I said it’s not because they don’t have a moral—
Robin:
But wait—it’s not arbitrary. I mean a 24-hour exam isn’t arbitrary. I mean,
there’s a reason why you said 24 hours per exam. And that means it’s not an
arbitrary rule.
Agnes:
It’s totally arbitrary. I give people different kinds of exams, and some of
them let them take as much time as they want, and some of them I arbitrarily
decided if we’re going to take one day for the exam.
Robin:
So here I mean, this is less about exams and more about sort of social
credit—that is, I am at least more interested in the plagiarism norms as
applied to a larger intellectual community rather than students taking their
exams. So the obvious rule would be whatever the rule your teacher has for
your exam, if you break that rule then you’re breaking the class’s rule.
Agnes:
Exactly. That’s why—
Robin:
So that’s not a general plagiarism rule. That’s just a rule about a class.
Agnes:
Exactly.
Robin:
Right. But we do, in more sense, have a larger social norm at least in larger
areas of intellectual work, that you know, if you have an idea you’re
presenting as new but it is not new, and not only is it not new, you know it’s
not new because you know where you got it from, and you’re not crediting where
you got it from, then that seems to be an illicit claiming of credit. So, and
because we often do give credit. So I mean, a lot of essays or something talk
about ideas, and they credit people for those ideas. And people are very
interested in making sure those credits are correct.
Agnes:
Right. I think of that interest as being listened. That is— So I mean one
thing is, you can’t fit the word plagiarism— it comes from the Latin plagium,
which is a net, and it means kidnapping. If I could kidnap someone else’s
idea, right, it’s like, Well this is my idea. And I think the paradigm of an
example of something that cannot be yours is an idea. Like it’s historical
fact that you— maybe you were the first one to think it. Maybe. I don’t know
that anyone has ever had really good reason to believe that, because of course
someone else could have thought it and just not told anyone. Right?
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
But okay, so really what it is, is like—
Robin:
First one to publish—
Agnes:
—you’re the first one to claim credit for it right? In a way there’s something
weirdly circular about that. It’s like I get credit because I was the first
one to claim credit for this. Or the first one to publish it, whatever. Right?
And to me that’s like a fiction, right? This— and so that’s why I brought up
the example of the cost—
Robin:
I mean so you know, there’s patent and copyright lawyers in law—
Agnes:
Yes.
Robin:
—and they also follow this plagiarism norm.
Agnes:
Well, they have— I mean so I think, you know, with respect to— We do have
legal sanctions for more specific categories. And those categories are about
things like other people being able to make money off of your idea, right. So
if I wanted to…
Robin:
Which means we have to label it your idea first, right?
Agnes:
Right. Absolutely. But so I think that…
Robin:
So your idea is a thing there. It’s not just a thing in an intellectual sort,
it’s another thing in the law of patent and copyright law.
Agnes:
Well what we can say is just, We have a law that if other people try to make
money off of this idea, then you get to get money from them or whatever,
right?
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
That’s what the law is, right? And I mean, we can make laws to kind of punish
behavior, any kind of behavior we want, right? And so we can decide we’ll all
be better off if we punish such and such a behavior.
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
Right? Probably, if you drive on the left side of the road in the United
States, you’re going to be punished by law, right? We have a law, you have to
drive on the right side of the road, right? And so if you punish— If you drive
on the left side of the road, you’ll be punished. But is there something
intrinsically wrong with driving on the left? No, it’s fine to drive. It’s
just, if other people do it—
Robin:
No, it’s not fine to drive on the left side when everybody else was driving on
the right side!
Agnes:
Right. And so you might say like, that’s sort of, you know, that’s why I
brought up the thing about the students, right? So there’s a game that we
play, right? We’re all playing a certain credit game.
Robin:
Yes.
Agnes:
And it’s quite possible that that game creates good incentives. Right? So it
might create incentives for people to come up to, let’s say, share their
ideas. (Because if I’m right, maybe I don’t want to say “come up with” ideas,
right?) So let’s say “share” their ideas. It might create those incentives.
Right? And so it’s a game that we’re playing, so other people are playing; you
should play along. I’m fine with that, right? But if we contrast it to our
previous topic, honesty—
Robin:
Yeah.
Agnes:
—right, so I think honesty is important. It’s actually objectively valuable.
And we have honesty norms because they’re tracking the moral reality.
Plagiarism norms is more like you get one day for the paper, or you drive on
the right side of the road, or whatever: We set up some convention and then
you’re not playing fair if you don’t follow the rules.
Robin:
So what this conversation is really about is the context-dependence or social
context of norms. That is, we agree that some norms are tied to very specific
social contexts, and they make sense in those contexts. And it’s less clear
that you would want to follow them outside those contexts. And other norms we
have are very broadly shared, like don’t murder or lie, and of course even
these very broadly shared norms have various exceptions and conditions and,
you know, metrics regarding them. And those often vary somewhat by context.
So
for example, it’s okay to kill people in war but not okay to murder them
otherwise. But like, what’s a war? You know, is a political civil war a war,
or is it a civil war if it’s declared? Or is it just— Do you protest, is that
allowed to be civil war? I mean, right, there’d be all these, you know, more
context-dependent conditions even about murder.
But you know, the
fundamental story is, Well in any one society you have some set of norms. And,
you know, there’s first the question, Should people follow the existing norms
in the society they’re in? And you can certainly make the case for specific
norms and societies and say, No, you shouldn’t follow that norm. That’s just
bad. And you know, that’ll make the norm go away—if it does, fine, because
that’s a bad norm. And other societies we might say, Well there’s a norm, and
if everybody keeps following this norm then you should too, because, you know,
it’s better than not having a norm.
But if there’s a better way— place
where you could get to some alternative set of norms, and that would— we
should try to coordinate to move there. And so you know, social innovation in
institutions is all about, you know, thinking about these alternatives. And I
might say, Well look, we have an existing set of plagiarism norms. If you’ve
got a new set of norms that you want to propose that we consider, I’m open to
that.
It’ll still be some work to try to get us to switch over, and it
might not be a good idea to just— individually, people to like copy stuff and
not tell people as the way that we approve of the switching the norm. That
might seem a little unfair, right? But still, I mean, you know, is your
complaint just that this isn’t a universal norm proven to be valuable in all
possible contexts, or that you have another particular set of norms we should
think of switching to?
Agnes:
So I don’t have another set that we should switch to. And maybe my case would
be more persuasive if I did. But I do have a kind of reason for thinking that
these norms are like mere arbitrary conventions rather than tracking a
reality. And by the way, I feel the same way, for instance, about privacy
norms. So what— and what I think about both of these cases, I think you should
follow them. Like, I think I should follow these norms.
Because I think
in general we have sort of implicit agreements with all the people around us
to behave in ways that, roughly speaking, abide by the norms that we’re all
under even if we don’t agree with them, until we can change people’s minds
about them. So, but the steps of changing people’s minds, that’s like a lot of
steps, probably more than my lifetime.
Robin:
Well, there’s one way to change people’s minds about a norm is simply just
stop following it and stop enforcing it.
Agnes:
Right. But if you individually stop following it, in many cases what you’re
doing is violating the norm, and so you’re violating an agreement that you
have with people. And I think you shouldn’t do that. You should persuade them
to adopt a different one.
Robin:
I mean sometimes, like you have laws that are on the books for a long time and
then people stop enforcing them. And you might say, Well, this isn’t an
agreement I’ve had; this law’s just been on the books for a long time. And
then you know, for example, you know, it’s been a long time since anybody
enforced laws against adultery, right? And you might say that’s still a norm
you’d want to obey, but it’s not a law anymore. Or there’s a lot of other sort
of laws in the books and there’s lots of places you can look these things up,
sort of arbitrary laws, right?
Agnes:
Yeah. I mean—
Robin:
So you might say, Don’t feel too bad about breaking the law that’s been on the
books for a while, but nobody’s been enforcing it for a while.
Agnes:
Yeah, I’m not talking about laws. So I’m talking more generally about norms.
And I guess I— You know, I do think everyone has to have some sense of sort
of, What is their social contract with the people around them, right? But
what— My thought is, your social contract isn’t limited to the set of norms
you personally endorse, right?
Robin:
Sure.
Agnes:
It’s gonna— There’s gonna be a larger set. How to define the space of that
larger set—because then there’s going to be stuff that’s still further out
where you think people are dumb that they’re all following this norm.
Robin:
But the easiest change to make from the status quo is to simply take an
existing law and delete it and not replace it with anything. And a simple path
to that is that you and other people just start ignoring that norm, and not
enforcing it and not sanctioning anybody who does enforce it. And that’s a
thing that’s happened a lot.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
In the past.
Agnes:
Right. And— But I’m not…
Robin:
So the question is, do you think if we just deleted the plagiarism norm but
didn’t replace it with something else, would that world be better?
Agnes:
There’s one respect in which it would be better. I don’t know that it would be
better overall. So you know, it’s a bit like the SAT or something, right? Like
you might think there are bad things about the SAT, and you might be— have
opposition to it, right? But then there are also costs to getting rid of the
SAT because we’re relying on these other things, right? That might be even
worse trackers of—
Robin:
Exactly.
Agnes:
—whatever. So if your question for me is like, Do you think this is a— You
know, that the system minus this norm would work better than the system with
this norm? I don’t know the answer, but maybe not. But I think that like, you
know, it’s sort of like you can get into a situation where you are relying—
You have like a system with these sort of junky parts or something, right? But
the junky parts are needed for the whole. And then you would have to rethink
the whole in a pretty radical way in order to improve the situation. And I’m
not doing any of that— I know you kind of want me to do it! [Laughs]
But
what I want to do is just explore why I think one of the parts is junky. And
because I think that people— That’s why I brought up the example of how you
can talk about how maybe terror— torture is okay, but you can’t talk about how
plagiarism might be okay, is that we have sort of sanctified or made sacred a
norm that isn’t a real intellectual norm, in my view. It isn’t like honesty or
truthfulness or inquisitiveness or rationality, or any of those things. It’s
just like driving on the right side of the road. And if suddenly we had no
norm about which side of the road you drove on, that would not be an improved
world!
But it’s specifically the reason why I want to say that’s the case
is that intellectual things are a very, very special category of things.
Namely, there are things where you can share them with other people and you
don’t have any less because you shared it. In fact in a way sometimes you have
more when you share them. And that’s like true of very few things out there.
Even sunsets, you know, it can be that there’s a crowd at the park.
Robin:
Okay, but you could say that’s also true of credit. The claim of credit is a
claim about who who did something first. And you can state that claim, and
it’s a factual statement, and I can share that claim with you and still share
it with somebody else.
Agnes:
So I think what the credit system does is it takes something whose distinctive
character and kind of sacred value is precisely that of being the very
opposite of zero-sum and turns it into a zero-sum game.
Robin:
You could say the same about music. The thing about music is I play you a song
and now you can play the song to somebody else. But then unless we have
copyrighted music exactly as a way to allow people to own his— I mean you
could say the same about a story: I tell you the story, you can tell the story
somewhere else, but we have copyright in stories. So—
Agnes:
Right, so I think we have things like copyright that— As I understand it, it
is kind of instrumental, it functions instrumentally in the incentive system
that you want people to be creating music and be able to make money from it.
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
Right? And you want people to be able to make money from their stories. And,
but it may be that we— Maybe we could do all of that without those incentives,
right? Like with other incentives. I mean, I get you’ll need some incentives
or other to make money. And— but— So, as I didn’t want to deny that the, you
know, these things have this role, in academia—especially in the, you know,
just crediting of ideas, especially in cases where what’s primarily sought
there is honor—like there is a point at which it seems to mostly be about just
wanting to mint a new currency or something, the currency of all—
Robin:
Well, it’s not new anymore. It’s pretty old by now.
Agnes:
Right. I’m—
Robin:
You’re imagining some counterfactual world long ago where it didn’t exist, but
we’ve minted many new things over the last few centuries that are no longer in
currency.
Agnes:
No, I just mean relative to the world in which it doesn’t exist, right? Like
in the case of copyright, what you’re doing is playing into the financial
system, right? I grant that something similar also happens with academia,
because your number of publications or whatever to get you—
Robin:
Yes. That’s saying something.
Agnes:
—but there is I think at least a sort of conceit in academia, right, that your
goals and that your fundamental understanding of your project is that you’re
trying to pursue the truth, and that you want to know things and understand
things and like, you will take—
Robin:
But giving credit doesn’t conflict with that. I mean they’re not false claims,
these kinds of credit.
Agnes:
Right, no, it doesn’t conflict with that. But it isn’t part of it in any way
except in the part that you have to stay alive and you want honor. Right? And
so the point is just that it’s not an intellectual norm, it’s a sort of norm
for how we take the intellectual and situate it in some way, in the..
Robin:
I think you’re making a move here that’s still similar to a move you made in
our last podcast.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
And it’s a relatively general point, and it’s a point of distinction, perhaps,
between economists and philosophers, which is why it might be worth pursuing
here. So you know, we economists will just tend to sort of flatten a whole
range of considerations into all, like, available things that we could
manipulate in order to get whatever ends you have, and not think of any of
them as more fundamental than the others.
So we might say, you know, the
intellectual world, we have a thing we want out of that: We want some sort of
intellectual progress in the long run. We’d like it to be true. We’d like it
to be tracking, you know, useful things. We'd like it to be shareable. We
would like it to be relatively easy to understand. We’d like it to be modular
so we can connect things together. There’s a whole bunch of things we would
like out of the intellectual project. You know, all else equal we’d like other
people to participate, right? I mean, we’d like a participatory intellectual
world, all else equal, right?
So we have a whole bunch of things we want.
And then we have a whole bunch of levers we can turn to manipulate the world
to get this thing— these things we want. And we economists just put them all
in those same two buckets, and don’t say, you know, of all the things we could
do, some might be more effective, some might be harder to monitor, some might
be more context-dependent. Some might, you know, be things that would change
the scale. But we’re just optimistically gonna say, Let’s just think about all
the things we could do, and try to do them as best we can to get the outcomes
we want.
And so I hear you saying, Well sure, this plagiarism rule helps
us get the outcomes we want, but it’s not fundamentally connected to the
thing. And we go, What’s the difference between fundamental versus not
fundamental? There’s just all these things we want, and there’s all these
things we do to get them, and why isn’t that just all there is?
Agnes:
We don’t agree on what the goals are. That is, I don’t think, for instance, in
our last conversation you said—
Robin:
Right. We don’t have to agree on what the goals are in order for this
framework to make sense.
Agnes:
Right. But what I’m saying is that those disagreements are not incidental. So
I don’t think that the goal of a university is intellectual progress. I don’t
think progress is a coherent goal. A goal has to be an endpoint and progress
isn’t an endpoint. So it’s a conceptually incoherent thing to have as your
goal.
Robin:
Oh, come on.
Agnes:
I think the goal of a university is knowing, right? And that goal is
instantiated. It’s not just a matter of the additions to knowledge that you’re
giving. It’s the knowing of the people in the university, it’s happening at—
It’s not something that is always going to happen in the future. It’s
something that’s happening in the present. And so the people who are knowing
things—people who are the students who are coming to know things, the teachers
who are activating their knowledge—all of that is achieving and realizing the
goal of the university.
Robin:
So but I see you as picking this thing as a bundle, and the way I was trying
to describe it is there are many goals that we share and don’t all agree on.
And this common enterprise we share is trying to in many ways accomplish all
of them to varying degrees. And in some sense we want to accomplish all of
them to varying degrees to the extent we can. And there isn’t the goal,
there’s just the many goals.
Agnes:
But I think it’s not an accident that you gave intellectual progress as the
goal, or as a goal— even if we just change it to a goal, it was the only goal
you cited, right? So it may be that some goals, a lot of the work is— comes in
coming to see them as a goal. That is, there’s sort of, let’s say, some goals
are more expensive and some are cheaper.
Robin:
Sure.
Agnes:
Right? And there’s a kind of psychological and personal investment that you
need in order to get certain goals in view. And I think in particular a lot of
the goals of the university are hard to have in view, and we lose hold of them
all the time, and we get redirected on to other goals that are not as good,
like, How many publications do I have, and how much honor do I have, etc.
And
so what these plagiarism—the plagiarism rules might be necessary, and they
might sort of function, but what they are doing is distracting us from our
fundamental project, and from understanding that fundamental project as a
non-zero-sum project.
Robin:
So it’s definitely true in many areas of human behavior that you have some
fundamental goals, and then you create subgoals, and you only really want to
achieve the subgoals because you think they promote the more fundamental
goals. So you definitely need to distinguish that. And yes, sometimes we get
distracted by subgoals, and not pay enough attention to other goals.
And
sometimes we don’t even know exactly which is which, because we just intuit
the practice. And we are presented various subgoals and trained how to achieve
the subgoals, and not even understand how these subgoals might be related to
the larger goals that we could more directly endorse.
So it’s definitely
true that, you know, in many areas of the world people sort of did— they lose
track of what matters. And they, you know, have some local metric, and, you
know, that’s not the fundamental thing. And that’s the sort of standard
problem with incentives: Economists will say, you know, you give a bunch of
people the incentive to achieve these subgoals, and they do, that doesn’t mean
the fundamental goals are achieved, right? Fine.
But still, you know,
there are these fundamental goals and there are many of them, and we don’t
agree on them. But I certainly think, you know, I’m happy to endorse the goal
you mentioned as a goal, but I’m just not willing to consider it exclusive as
the only goal among the many goals that, you know, these institutions see
themselves as trying to achieve, or should.
Agnes:
But in a way I think we’d be fine. I mean, I think— Here’s one way to put this
agreement. Say one of the things that universities currently seek to do is to
allocate credit for ideas.
Robin:
Yes.
Agnes:
That’s one of their goals. And—
Robin:
But it may be a subgoal.
Agnes:
Right, right, right, exactly. Well, that’s my point is, so I see that goal as
very strictly a subgoal. Namely, if there were some more efficient way of
achieving the fundamental goals we could get rid of that. And it could be that
nobody gets credit and nothing is wrong with that, or that’s a good world.
Robin:
Okay, so I mean, if we get personal: I have these grand visions for reforming
intellectual worlds, and they are mainly for the purpose of intellectual
progress. And if we have time we could go into my defending that that’s a
coherent thing and a valuable thing. But I think many of our readers will get
that enough that I don’t have to belabor it right now.
But there— I have
to admit, upon examining universities and academia, it achieves other goals
that I’m less thrilled with. And I think actually the dominant goal, the
dominant function of academia in society is to let people affiliate with
impressive people—credentialed, impressive people. So students want to go to a
university, and people say, Ooh, that’s a good university, you must be a good
student. And for that they want professors to be credentialed as impressive
people, and they don’t actually care what intellectual progress they’ve made.
Or even how— what they know. What they care is that their given credential is
impressive.
It’s, an elite reporter wants to call up a professor to
interview them. Why? Because they put that name and university as the line
next to the quote. It’ll be more impressive to the readers who like to read
articles with impressive quotes. And funders like to give money to impressive
projects and people, and you know, and affiliate with institutions. And when
people say, What did you do with the money? They say, Well, we gave it to
Harvard. And these people— look at all these news articles about them! And
people say, “Yes!”
And honestly, it is a thing people want. And if— and
our institutions are actually achieving it pretty well, in terms of letting
people affiliate with credential impressiveness and become impressive by
association. And it works! It’s not, you know, producing necessarily— And this
can be done even if nobody really knows that much, and if they never
accumulate more knowledge. And even if they lie! I mean, they can still be
impressive in lying. And so this, this can all work.
So I feel like,
okay, I have to compromise and say, Yeah, okay, that’s a purpose people want,
then yes, we— our institution should achieve that. But I also want
intellectual progress. So I’m open to trying to find better institutions which
could both give them this thing they want that I don’t want so much, and also
produce the stuff I like. And so if I’m going to be a practical reformer, I
have to come up with solutions that try to give many of the people the things
they’re getting out of these institutions.
You know, I want to reform
college, I probably have to give 20-year-olds a place where they can go meet
other 20-year-olds and party, because a lot of 20-year-olds like that, right?
If you’re going to reform college and you’re not going to give 20-year-olds
that, a lot of them aren’t going to pick it.
Agnes:
So I think it’s a really interesting meta question, which way are you going to
be more persuasive: One where you’re sort of willing to compromise, and you
say, Look, you have these goals that are totally stupid and I see as
completely valueless, but I get that you’re super into them in some kind of
impressiveness fetish that you have. And I’m going to give you some of your
trash thing so that I can get my good thing, and then we’ll both have gotten
something, right? So that’s like one kind of speech act, right?
And I
don’t know if you’ve ever tried this kind of speech with like one of your
children, or a close friend, or wife, but I find that this is not actually
very persuasive to people, and that actually, as a matter of fact, if I go to
people and I say, Let me just tell you why a lot of the plagiarism norms, and
a lot of the ideas you have about credit that you might even hold sacred and
treat as really important—that they’re actually not as good as you think they
are. But you tell me. You prove it to me. Show me that they’re good. Right?
It’s not actually obvious to me that that second route is less persuasive.
Robin:
So I haven’t heard that from you yet. I mean, I’ve heard like we can’t prove
that it’s needed in all contexts. But I haven’t heard you tell me the negative
consequences of the plagiarism norm, right?
Agnes:
Yeah, so—
Robin:
What goes— What do you see going wrong?
Agnes:
It’s that you’re turning something whose fundamental and distinctive value is
in being non-zero-sum into a zero-sum game, and thereby cheapening it and
making it more like all the other things that are worse than it.
Robin:
But you could make that argument about music.
Agnes:
Yes. And I think, like, if we can find another way to do it with the music,
that would be good too. I think a lot of people aren’t that comfortable with
art and music being sold in certain ways, and there being such restrictions on
them.
Robin:
So to an economist this sounds an awful lot like a common complaint, which is
you economists are polluting our pure, high minded stuff with your damn
selfish incentives.
Agnes:
Yes. So I mean— and—
Robin:
You economists ought to understand that, Sure, there’s lots of selfish people
in the world, and they need incentives, but we pure people over here, if you
would just leave us alone we would do our pure idealistic thing and we don’t
need incentives over here. They just get in the way because we’re good people.
[Laughs]
Agnes:
I never said the other people need them either. Right? But I do think that it
matters what— Look, even economists are going to, whatever, not tend to pay
their children to do stuff. And so like it’s all— There’s all the question of
where do you bring in the incentives? And I’m giving you a reason why in this
particular domain…
Robin:
All I hear is the pollution reason, that somehow incentives are polluting the
purity of the zero-sumness— of the non-zero-sumness.
Agnes:
So, well the other part of the argument is that the— If you take the
non-zero-sum point of view and then try to get into view, What is of value
there? Right? About the kind of sharing of knowledge and having a community in
which knowledge is shared? That value is, it’s like hard to track with your
mind, it’s hard to get a grip on, unlike the idea of progress or adding stuff,
which is much easier to track, right?
So even within the university
there’s a bunch of goals, right? Often we can get into view improvement as a
goal, that’s an easier thing than to get into view just instantiating a value,
that second thing is harder. Just like, you know, coming up with a new piece
of music or whatever, it’s easy to see that as valuable versus enjoying an
existing piece of it. That’s harder.
So my point is that there’s— It’s
expensive to value this thing, right? And so I think often when people are
talking about purity, and worries about purifying/sullying something, the way
you should— what you should translate that into is, here’s a goal that we have
trouble seeing as valuable. And we only get it into view like maybe like three
minutes of every day. And one thing we’re constantly trying to do is get it
more and better into view, and we’re willing to like pay a lot to get that
goal into view, we’re willing to make other sacrifices. And when I say you’re
sullying it, what I mean is you’re making it difficult for me to get that goal
into view.
Robin:
So professors have offices and they have jobs, and to a first approximation
those are zero-sum. Like you have your office, nobody else can have your
office. You have your job, somebody else doesn’t have your job. So by letting
professors have offices and jobs, we are sullying with— this high-minded
pursuit of this zero-sum element of allocating offices and jobs. Surely,
therefore, professors shouldn’t have jobs or offices.
Agnes:
So I mean, I think like, if you want to say… There might be circumstances
under which I’d be amenable to that argument, but I—
Robin:
But not usually!
Agnes:
I’m not usually, and so I think that it, you know, it matters that what we’re
doing here is we’re saying like not only do the professors need some way of
sort of like living their lives, while they perceive this value…
Robin:
But do they really need offices for that? I mean, they would still be alive if
they didn’t have offices.
Agnes:
Well no, but I mean, they need to, you know— The activity of thought is a
physical activity, right?
Robin:
You can do it at home! Why do they need to go in the office?
Agnes:
So you need to have a place. You might be, and many professors do, but if you
have several kids at home like I do, this can be a challenge. So…
Robin:
But that’s a context-dependent, contingent consideration, right? Just like
plagiarism is.
Agnes:
Right. So I guess my thought is that it’s like, suppose we… I mean, it seems
to be the more relevant, let’s say, challenge case would be, we have awards
for professors, right? Where like you’re the— you— well, you can—
Robin:
Or publications? Why should these things be published? Why don’t they just all
go sit on an archive server, and why should we distinguish some papers as
published? There’s a limited number of slots in the top journals. Why should
we make that a zero-sum element in academia, where only some papers get to be
in the top journals?
Agnes:
Yeah, I don’t think that’s great either. I mean, you know, if there’s a system
where we can— and I think in some fields it’s moving towards a system of just
kind of, you know…
Robin:
No, actually, I mean there are fields where most people get their access to
the papers through the servers, but they all still have the award element in
the journals, right?
Agnes:
Right, right.
Robin:
And so prestige is allocated through the journals.
Agnes:
And so like, you know, I guess the way that I would see all of this is it’s a
kind of concession, right?
Robin:
Yes. Yes! And that’s what economists do: We say like, You had your ideal image
of things but you forgot people being selfish and mean sometimes—
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
—so we need institutions that are a concession to people’s selfishness.
Agnes:
In a way I’m fine with that, it’s just that what I want to do is to
distinguish that sometimes we go all the way to creating norms, right, to do
that kind of work. But there are other norms we have that are real norms,
where they’re not concessions—they’re actually ways of tracking the value
itself. And I think of honesty as being such a norm.
Robin:
Okay, so I see you then as thinking that even though we humans are not the
angels we’d like to think ourselves are, and sometimes we’re selfish and
sometimes we’re biased and mean, there are these counterfactual creatures that
we like to imagine. And for those creatures, they would need norms: the norms
would be useful for those creatures, and those creatures would have
high-minded tasks, and they would have names for things, and rules that would
help them achieve their tasks. And we actual humans should try to talk in
those terms.
Agnes:
Yeah, so maybe the— One way to put it is like you have this idea of we’re not
the angels we like to think of ourselves as, as though thinking of oneself as
an angel were such an easy thing to do and so readily available to people. And
I think, No, the challenge is to think of yourself as an angel. That’s like
the goal, right? But like, a lot of the time our thinking is just occupied
with lowly things. And we’re trying to move into that more angelic move to
become better, right?
And so like, but of course at the same time as we
try to move into the more angelic mode and actually try to think of ourselves—
try to think our way to becoming more like the angels, and less thinking like
them, we also have to make concessions along the way because we have to
survive long enough to get to that other side. Right?
And so yes, I think
it would be fair to say there are the norms that the angels would still hold
on to even once they’re angels, and then there are the ones where they’re like
ladders that we hope to throw away one day. And all I’m saying is that these
plagiarism ones are more like ladders that we have to throw away.
And so
I think there are real consequences here about your emotional response, right,
to the violation of the norm. Because I think if the norm is merely a thing to
like coordinate our baser natures with this other thing, right, then it’s
still bad if people violate it. It’s bad basically because they’re cheating.
Right? And you should be annoyed with them in the way that you are annoyed at
cheaters.
But I think a lot of people— the way they feel about somebody,
you know, claiming credit for their idea or something goes even deeper than…
Like they feel like, you know, something profound was stolen from them that
was rightly theirs in a kind of moralistic sense. People get very indignant
about it. And my thought is like, there was never anything that was yours. We
just decided to play this game as though the thing was yours.
Robin:
But now you’re saying people should not feel morally indignant about
violations of rules that would not need to exist if people were the angels we
might wish they were.
Agnes:
I’m saying we should feel as indignant as we would if somebody takes an extra
day with their exam. But we should understand that— it as being that kind of
rule.
Robin:
But I think— I mean there’s large and small violations, right? So if everybody
were angels, nobody would speed because they’d all judge the proper speed to
be safe. We only have speeding rules because people are selfish and they speed
when they can get away with it, but some speeding rules are bigger than
others.
But you can be morally indignant at somebody speeding. That seems
perfectly reasonable. They’re speeding on the road, and they’re getting away
with it, they’re endangering people. Why can’t I be indignant?
Agnes:
Sure, I think you can. And I think that in general what people do is they get
indignant over rule violations. Because that indignation is, it’s like an
internalized form of policing, right? So it’s like, I’m— By getting indignant
at you, I in some sense at least have the feeling that I’m enforcing the law.
Your speeding in another car makes me it easy to have them.
Robin:
Yes. Well, if it makes you inclined to actually enforce it more, should the
opportunity arise, when the blood boils—
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
When situations come up to call them on it or complain about it, or maybe pull
over and call a cop or something, you might be more likely to do it.
Agnes:
Right. But I think that like… And I mean, maybe the plagiarism case is an
interesting case, because you know it’s one thing when somebody violates the
rules and thus cheats, right? And you might be angry at them because you were
playing by the rules, right? And then it’s another thing if you feel that you
were personally wronged, right? And the plagiarism case is an overlap of those
two things: If you plagiarize me, that I had this idea, that’s like my idea,
right?
Robin:
Well if you come and steal my parked car, you know, or if you steal somebody
else’s car, I can be indignant in your stealing their car or my car, because
it’s part of the system of property. And I say property is an arbitrary system
that we have only because we’re not angels. But hey, we’re not angels. We need
property. So, you stole my car!
Agnes:
Right, right. And I mean I guess I think that like, you know, it does make
sense that people are indignant over rule violations, and then are more
indignant when the rule violation disadvantages them in particular.
Robin:
Of course.
Agnes:
Actually I’m not 100% sure that does make sense. Now that I think about it,
it’s certainly what happens.
Robin:
Yeah.
Agnes:
If you’re really indignant over a rule violation—
Robin:
Well, it’s a division of labor—I mean if something goes wrong, if the person
most harmed doesn’t complain, why should the rest of us complain? We might
want to at least see that they’re not happy. Because sometimes there’s rules
and they’re violated, but the person doesn’t mind it being violated, so why
should the rest of us? So that’s often a rule of thumb about violations: You
know, does the person involved want to complain? Say an assault, right? If I
hit you and you mind, then you can complain about assault. But sometimes
people get hit and they don’t mind, and the rest of us aren’t going to go
enforce assault rules against them; we’re gonna say, Well, this is the person
who got hit, they will.
Agnes:
That’s interesting. So I mean it seems like what we want is not necessarily
people following the rules, but people following the rules in all the cases
where somebody won’t— will complain if they don’t follow the rules.
Robin:
Sure. Well, like for example trespassing, right? You know, what is
trespassing? When somebody is on your property and you didn’t let them on your
property. If you let them on your property it’s not trespassing.
Agnes:
Well that’s a special case because then they haven’t broken a rule. But I
mean, you might—
Robin:
But didn’t you make the rule exactly that you do something and they mind?
Agnes:
But that isn’t the, like…
Robin:
I mean, we can phrase the rule itself that way: Assault is where you hit
somebody and they mind.
Agnes:
Well, I don’t think we could phrase it— it would be too self referential if we
phrase it “Assault is if you hit somebody and then they like legally
complain,” because they could mind, for instance, but want not to say anything
or something, right? So you can’t deal with minding— like, is it only assault
if they complained about its being assault? You know, kind of like it’s money
if you think it’s money. I don’t think we want the law to be that
self-referential. It was, we wanted the crime to be like punching someone
unprovoked, or I don’t know, what is assault, hitting someone.
Robin:
So clearly rape is an example of like consent is an excuse.
Agnes:
Right—right. I mean, well, in that case, but that’s like—
Robin:
Just like trespassing.
Agnes:
Right. But that’s— I think that’s a different case. Because for instance you
could consent to sex with someone and then later mind, or something. So the
minding and the consenting are like the same thing, right? And so in general I
think that, like with trespassing, like it can be you didn’t give them
permission to be on your land, right? And they are trespassing. And in fact
the last five times someone did it you complained, but this time it turns out
you don’t care. They’re wearing a nice dress and you’re just enjoying watching
them walk across your lawn. Right? And so it’s odd that you—
Robin:
Okay, but I think we’re getting distracted from the more fundamental point
here which is just about, you want to make a distinction between rules we have
which are an accommodation to our lesser natures, and see those as lesser
rules than the rules we have which we would want to adopt even if we were the
most ideal creatures, or more ideal creatures that we can imagine.
Agnes:
Yeah, I think the thing that I’m reacting to maybe most fundamentally is like
the place that plagiarism plays like on syllabi and stuff. It is sort of
presented as though it were the fundamental academic value and norm and like,
we’re extremely—
Robin:
I mean, fundamental is different than strong, right?
Agnes:
Yeah, but like—
Robin:
I mean, certainly nobody thinks it’s the fundamental value.
Agnes:
I mean, I think that it— For instance there’s a lot of stuff you can do wrong
in a class, but it’s plagiarizing that will like get you kicked out of school.
Robin:
I think that’s because it’s relatively easy to enforce; that is, it’s a nice
clear line. But there’s a lot— most of the other things are relatively
ambiguous.
Agnes:
I mean, I don’t know what you think of as being hard to enforce. I’ve had
situations— I had a student once who was so disruptive in class, he would come
in and out of the classroom maybe 50 times over the course of a class, he
would sit with his back to me, he would talk during class. Okay, I, you know,
I was like, This is creating a big problem for my class, right?
Robin:
But we haven’t drawn a line about how many times you’re allowed to walk in and
out of the class. So we didn’t draw a rule based on that disruption.
Agnes:
It can be extremely—
Robin:
It’s hard to draw that line.
Agnes:
It can be extremely hard to say what what counts as plagiarism or not. There’s
very fine lines about sort of copying, copying wording, how much do you copy,
what if you have other stuff in there, is something totally plagiarized. Like
there’s definitely cases where it’s much easier for me to recognize the bad
behavior than it is for me to recognize something as plagiarism.
Robin:
So I mean, if I stand back and just look at academia in all its glory and
misery, and I say, like, What’s wrong with this thing, and like, what should
be better? This just doesn’t seem to meet near— anywhere near the top of the
things that I could see wrong. This seems like, you know, picking a complaint
about a certain way people talk about plagiarism. You don’t object to the rule
itself because you don’t have another one to replace it with and you’re not so
sure you want to take it away, even just to squash it—you just like dislike
how much reverence people are giving to it.
Agnes:
Yeah.
Robin:
And you know, I would say, Well, you know, come up with something else that we
should give preference or relevance to, or a bigger change, and that seems
much more productive. You know, I have some suggestions like that and you may
too, but I mean, wouldn’t it be more productive to just ask, What are the
biggest things that are wrong with academia?
Agnes:
I think that anything that helps you understand things better is productive.
And I’m not— Like you’re always looking for like the most leverage or
something for a given thing. But I’m not always doing that. And I think the
reason I’m not doing it is that quite often the leverage comes in a place that
is unexpected for me. And so I can start thinking about something and then I
get leverage that I didn’t expect.
So, but the thing that you’re supposed
to get out of thinking about this is that if we have kind of wrongly
centralized a particular value, we’re over-punishing it, we’re
over-coordinating on this—like we’re acting like this is what binds us
together. That is both encouraging us not to notice the more fundamental
things that bind us together, and in fact, this particular sort of value, and
this idea of credit, is one that makes it hard to get what are the most
fundamental values into view.
Robin:
But I feel like your talking about it here is doing the distraction. That is,
I think most academics don’t think much about plagiarism exactly because they
share it, so it seems so obvious to them. So it doesn’t actually distract them
much. An hour talking about it now will be making them think more about
plagiarism than they ever did in the last ten years, because they don’t think
about it much.
Agnes:
No, I don’t think it’s bad to think about it. I think it’s bad to unthinkingly
see it as a profound sin.
Robin:
But you’ve made me think a little bit more, and at the moment I go, you know,
I like our plagiarism rules!
Agnes:
[Laughs]
Robin:
Just like, they seem fine to me! I don’t see the problem with them.
Agnes:
Well maybe I shouldn’t have talked about it with you, then! [Laughs]
Robin:
I mean, I could point to other things I think are bigger things to think
about. Like most fundamentally, the fundamental mechanism we have in academia
is we credential some people as good, and then we ask them to choose who the
other good people are. That is, that the most fundamental mechanism is peer
review of various sorts, but you know, that’s the core mechanism in academia.
That’s how we decide who gets what jobs, who gets what grants, who gets what,
you know, journal publications, etc.
Agnes:
I think the core mechanism in academia is teaching because that’s how people
learn stuff. And what we’re about is knowing.
Robin:
Okay, but we need a mechanism by which, when people compete, we decide who
wins.
Agnes:
What I’m saying is that’s a bad framework for thinking about like the
intellectual realm in general. And it’s exactly that kind of framework that
centralizing plagiarism sort of suggests.
Robin:
So I mean, I would say the larger question is, we have these goals we want to
achieve, and we have, say, a budget—either the NSF or something—and we have to
decide how to allocate this budget in order to achieve our goals. That would
be the economic framing of the question.
And we have not just a money
budget, we have prestige budgets of various sorts to hand out. And, you know,
many different people and institutions say, If you give the money to us, or
the prestige to us, we will do this teaching, or we will do this research, and
we will do this accrediting and credentialing. And the fundamental question
is, Who do we believe? Who do we trust? We can’t just—do we do it at
random?
And so I would say the fundamental mechanism by which we answer
this question, Who do we give the resources to to achieve these ends that we
want to achieve?, is this peer-review mechanism. That is we we find the people
who have been by consensus considered the most prestigious or the most
knowledgeable, etc., on their topic, and we say, Who do you think the money
should go to? Who do you think the job should go to? Or, How do you think
students should be taught?
All of these different key questions about
what exactly to do are answered fundamentally by asking the most prestigious
people what do they think, and then we just do what they say. That’s pretty
much how the whole thing goes. And so once you even say this out loud, I think
it should be obvious the kind of things that could go wrong with a system like
this. And I think that’s one of the most fundamental things to ask about
academia, is, Does that go wrong? How often does it go wrong? Can we think of
something better?
Agnes:
So like one of the words that shows up a lot when you talk is like prestige,
and impress, and you said, you know, people are trying to affiliate with
impressive people—
Robin:
Credentialed impressive people.
Agnes:
—and credential and reputation, right? And so all those words are kind of like
words that are, I would say secondary words. Like they’re all words that it’s
like, there’s the appearance of x, right? So being impressive is being able to
appear as though you were x. Maybe knowledgeable, right? It depends on what
you’re impressive for. So my thought is, you have never reached the
fundamental level of analysis about something if you’re using any of those
words.
Robin:
So I disagree strongly in the sense that I’m saying, well, from the
institution design point of view, from the person giving away money point of
view, they will have to give away money on the basis of appearances because
they will not see past appearances to fundamentals. So we have to design
institutions in terms of appearances. That’s a fundamental constraint on
institution design.
Agnes:
I mean, you know, one question then maybe is like— So like in this
conversation I don’t believe we’re designing an institution. That is, I mean I
suppose there’s a small chance that some people who, you know, decide things
may listen to this podcast and then decide to change how they— But it’s like
that’s very unlikely, right?
So in a way it’s odd that you want to adopt
the framework of doing x when we’re not doing x. That is, my framework is we
want to understand what is the university actually for, where it may be that
adopting the institution design point of view doesn’t actually answer that
question very well. And given that we’re not designing an institution, what
about that framework?
Robin:
But you know, I’ve said the institution is for all the different things we
might want to achieve with it. And it’s a practical question, which of them we
can achieve? How much? And at what tradeoff with the other goals?
So I
don’t think there is a fundamental question of what the institution is for.
Institutions are never for particular things. They might happen to more often
achieve a particular thing that people might more want them to achieve that
particular thing, but fundamentally they are for whatever we want them to be
for.
What is doctoring for? Well…
Agnes:
Health. That’s the answer, if there’s just an answer. [Laughs] And
universities are for knowledge. So I guess I just think I have no idea what
we’re doing with these institutions. If we’re like, we don’t see them as
having any goals, how are we even improving them? We don’t even know what is
improved?
Robin:
No, but we might just have a set of goals, all of which we would like to
achieve with them, and one of them might be the biggest one. And that’s fine
to focus our attention on that. But it is not a choice we have.
Agnes:
Right, I mean in a way for me, it’s odd to even be like, What are we doing?
It’s like, well, we are talking, right? And now— you know—
Robin:
But you were taking the same frame with respect to plagiarism. You’re standing
back and asking us to take a different attitude toward plagiarism, right?
Agnes:
But I guess I’m not saying that as from the point of view of like if I were a
university administrator. I’m saying like as a professor who— That’s why I
brought up the question of, you know, within courses: Because I do assign
papers for courses, right? And so I have to think about the question, Am I
going to allow my students to plagiarize the papers they write for me? And you
know, like, I think, Well, there are gonna be educational harms if I do that.
So I don’t want to allow that.
And then I have to think, Well, as a
researcher, whatever, shall I plagiarize other people’s work? And then I
think, No, there’s this this game that everyone’s playing and I gotta play
along. Right? And so I’m thinking from my point of view as being in this
system and my various goals, right? Where does plagiarism fit?
And I
think even given all that conformity that I’ve just described—I think I want
to conform to the system—there’s still like a move to be made in terms of
seeing that these norms are a bit hollow, a bit artificial, a bit
conventional. And in fact, they kind of—especially when I unthinkingly follow
them and unthinkingly, you know, put them in a special category where
students, for instance, get kicked out of school for violating them, what that
does is incline me to become not attuned to the most fundamental, most
important and most expensive-to-maintain-one’s-attention-on goals of the
university.
Robin:
But surely what we want is for many people to change the perspective, not just
me in particular or you in particular.
Agnes:
Well, people are listening to us—
Robin:
Hopefully.
Agnes:
—so maybe this will change their mind.
Robin:
But I mean, surely you—
Agnes:
You want to make them change their minds through institutions?
Robin:
I want you to accept the idea that when we think about our social practices
and our institutions and our norms, that we are going to do both diagnosis and
prognosis. And with— when we do diagnosis, we are not going to be very sure
which particular prognosis exactly will be invoked for any one diagnosis.
First, we want to just structure the situation and find the main things going
on, and to, you know, categorize things correctly and identify the core
processes.
And, but we want to do that with an eye toward identifying
problems, because that’s why we have progress. Because progress is— would be
figuring out how to solve the problems. And if there are no problems to solve,
maybe there’s no point to thinking about it.
So, but solutions come in a
wide range of difficulty. Some solutions can be implemented by any one person
all by themselves, and nobody else; they don’t even need to consult their
spouse or their department chair. Other solutions might require a whole
department to coordinate together. Still other solutions might require a whole
profession or journal together, or their university. Some might require a
nation of the world to coordinate.
And of course, once we understand that
some require larger coordination, all else equal, we will be less interested
in those. Nevertheless if they have bigger potential gains we might eye them
and still think maybe we’ll go for that.
And so fundamentally we just
have to enter this process, you know, looking for diagnoses that would lend
themselves to prognosis. And then when we have a clear enough diagnosis, we
then start to consider specific solutions that might be offered. And then we
will prefer the solutions that are easier to implement, of course, but we will
also want to just think about solutions that are testable or easy to test.
So
we might come up with a solution that would require a widespread adoption, but
could be tested on a small scale. It wouldn’t be— have its full effect on
small scale, but it could be shown to work on a small scale, then you might go
to the larger community and say, How about we all do this? Like we tried to
have an academic community where there was no credit, and this is how it went,
and now maybe the rest of you should realize you don’t need credit as much as
you thought because hey, it seemed to work here. And, you know, that’s the
sort of thing you could consider.
So I would just suggest that we— you
just enter the diagnosis phase in an open minded sense of like, We’re not sure
what kinds of fixes we’re going to plan on suggesting, and sometimes we may
decide the small— none of the small-scale fixes seem feasible, effective, and
the only thing that will work will be larger-scale coordination. And at that
point you could decide to dump it because it’s not worth continuing, or you
might decide this is important enough that you would then start to explore the
larger-scale solutions.
Agnes:
So your basic mindset and your basic framing of the situation is like
problem-solving.
Robin:
Yes.
Agnes:
And I’m not antipathetic to that, but I don’t think it’s the only thing one
can do with speech. And I’m not always sure that it’s the thing that makes the
most sense to do in inquisitive conversations, but I don’t want to deny that
it’s a thing you can do and it’s a valuable thing you can do.
So maybe
it’s a little bit like your multiple goals thing—like you say you want me to
accept a whole bunch of stuff. Just now you’re like I should accept all this
stuff—and I want to say, Well, I may be willing to sort of accept it if I can
also accept some other stuff. It’s not always clear to me that the biggest,
most fundamental and most important social changes are going to happen in the
kind of top-down way where the institution is going to get redesigned, right?
Maybe sometimes, but like that’s itself a question.
Robin:
Sure.
Agnes:
But we should stop now. But just as a last word, can I have the last word?
Robin:
Just one word?
Agnes:
No.
Robin:
No.
Agnes:
The last sentence.
Robin:
Okay, last sentence.
Agnes:
Yeah, the last sentence is, I want to give a shout out to Brian Fry, from whom
I plagiarized all of my views about plagiarism.
Robin:
Tada!