Pink and Purple
Agnes:
Hi Robin.
Robin:
Hi Agnes!
Agnes:
So you know, we just talked about the criminal justice system. So I thought
we’d change topics to which are the prettiest colors? Somebody who—
Robin:
Similarly important topic!
Agnes:
Yeah, exactly! So I’m gonna give you my argument telling you which are the
prettiest colors and then you can respond to it. So the first premise of my
argument is that the specialists in any domain are going to be the best at
distinguishing what is making the relevant distinctions in that domain, right?
So you know, those who specialize in x, and especially like, value x, and
spend a lot of time engaging with x, are good at like telling what is x-ish
for any x. That’s the first premise.
And the second part is that we do
have a set of specialists in prettiness, which is little girls. So little
girls, they like all the things that are pretty, like unicorns and princesses
and fairies and like, dresses, flowers. Right? And then the third premise is
that little girls tend to like pink and purple. And so therefore pink and
purple, we should trust them—they’re kind of like the experts—that these are
in fact the prettiest colors. That’s my argument.
Robin:
Okay, so I mean, the first thing that happens is you throw me and I say, Well,
you know, why do I care what the prettiest colors are exactly? That is, I’m
looking for a way to operationalize this question, to connect it to other
questions I might care about so that I can try to figure out how to decide
even what these words mean. Right?
Agnes:
Okay, so you don’t care which are the prettiest colors.
Robin:
I don’t immediately, but I might like want to think about it. But then so if I
just sort of said, Well, you’re going to have an event, say, where people who
like prettiness are there, and we want to know what colors to decorate that
event in, well now I’ve got an anchor here. I have a certain set of people I’m
trying to please. And… Or I thought maybe there was a feeling, like, of
prettiness, right? Like, and so I wanted to evoke that feeling, right? Maybe
somebody is down, and maybe somebody says pretty things will bring this person
up. And now I have an anchor, okay—I want to bring this person up. So I want
to put pretty things around this person. Right?
And so those would be
like grounded versions of the question that I can relate to better, because
now I can import a whole structure for each— each of the questions like brings
in a structure that helps me answer the question, and helps me think about how
to answer. Whereas when you say, What’s the prettiest color? I’m sort of at a
loss because this word pretty has so many connotations.
Agnes:
So like one reason why I find that to be a strange response from you is that
you talk about things like aliens that we’re not going to communicate with,
and these brain emulations that maybe have a 10% chance of happening like a
long time in the future and stuff, where in a lot of these cases there is
nothing that we can do. There’s nothing to be done in relation to the
question, but you’re just interested in the question of what will the future
look like, maybe?
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
Like, what— It probably won’t look like this, but it could look like this—a
tiny chance.
Robin:
So to my mind at least, the words are anchored, like, in a context which gives
them the meaning that you could then use to answer the question. So I’d have a
similar issue by like saying like, you know, is music or dance better
conducive to love? And I might go, Well, which kind of love? Because there’s a
lot of kinds of love and people use it in different ways. And I might, like,
be looking for a way to give a more specific version of the concept that I can
connect to these other concepts of say, music or dance.
Or literature,
say. If you might say like, which is more conducive to love, music or
literature? And so again I’d be trying to turn it into a more concrete
question like, What should you use to serenade her: music or literature? If
you’re trying to, you know, to impress somebody, that would be a different
thing. Or which should we have more of a wedding? Maybe we say we have too
much music and not enough literature at weddings, because literature would be
better at promoting love at a wedding. I mean, again, then I can get my teeth
around it more.
Agnes:
So I mean, see for me with that case it’s like conduciveness to love is a
quite alien property to me. Like I’ve never thought about what it would be for
something to be conducive to love. So I agree for you to be puzzled. You know,
what does it mean? And maybe what it means is it’s an instrument for the
bringing about of love, right? And then we want to know which kind is it going
to bring about? Or maybe it’s supposed to keep love going or whatever,
right?
So you’re right: That’s a weird property to ask about. But I feel
like prettiness is not such a weird property to ask about. Like I feel like
it’s one of the properties that is sort of immediately available and familiar
to everyone. You use the word “pretty,” kind of everyone knows what you mean.
So it doesn’t seem like I’m making such a strange or alien claim.
Robin:
So I mean, in most contexts where people talk about things being pretty they
tend to make choices about what’s pretty, and they aren’t usually looking for
other people’s advice about what’s pretty.
Agnes:
But you always care what other people think, right? That’s one of your views.
Robin:
Okay, well, so if we wanted to know, you know, if I wear this dress or that
dress, which one will look prettiest, then we might depend on the context: So
if you’re a grade-school teacher—
Agnes:
Yeah.
Robin:
—or you’re going to a, you know, an expensive ball, that would evoke different
sort of audiences who might judge prettiness. But then it would be less
important which audience is the best judge of prettiness because we want to
know what this audience will judge prettiness to be there.
Agnes:
But you might— for instance you might think, Look: Adults become sort of like,
you know, jaded and conformist in their aesthetic tastes, especially with
respect to, say, clothing, right? And they all start to look alike and they
lose even an interest in looking like beautiful, right? And then so you might
like, you know, look to a population that kind of took a native interest in
prettiness, right?
And you know, someone might similarly, they go to a
restaurant— like they go, they’re in a foreign country and they want to have
the best version of some kind of food, right? And they might not be able to
tell that it’s the best one, right? They don’t have defined palettes to
discriminate, but they still care. Which is the— But they might ask for a
recommendation, Where do I get the best version of this dish? And they want to
have the best one, right?
And so similarly, you might want to actually
have the prettiest, like, clothing or wall decorations or whatever. And maybe
if you start doing that you’ll become more attuned to its prettiness and even
learn to appreciate it more, as you might with the food, right? But people
regularly take a kind of interest in having the version of something whose
“bestness” is not immediately apparent to them, but they sort of trust the
experts: wine, food, etc. And why not with prettiness too?
Robin:
In this context there’s the interesting phenomenon that supposedly these
experts become worse over time…
Agnes:
Yes.
Robin:
…at this thing they’re they’re supposedly expert at.
Agnes:
Yes, that is interesting.
Robin:
And that’s more paradoxical about it, right? So if we were talking about
70-year-old versions of these people who after a lifetime had especially the
judgment of prettiness, we’d be less puzzling here.
Agnes:
Yes.
Robin:
But here we’re sort of— So here we’re positing some degrading of their ability
to discern, or their interest in discerning or something, that says something
especially interesting about this concept. It says that people can’t seem to
maintain an interest in it or maintain an ability to discern it, which then
might speak to its usefulness: Like, well, who will want prettiness if these
people who once wanted it, they don’t want it so much anymore? Who does want
prettiness?
Agnes:
Right, so you know one thing that I might say to you under these circumstances
is something I say to my undergraduate students in say, if I’m teaching The
History of Philosophy I, okay—so this is Introduction to History of
Philosophy—so we’re reading Plato and Aristotle, but for many people this is
their first philosophy class. And often I’ll put an argument on the board,
right? And I’ll say premise one, premise two, premise three, conclusion, and
then I’ll turn to the class and I’ll say, Okay, responses.
And I’ll get a
lot of different kinds of responses. Some of them will be like, I don’t even
see why we’re arguing about this. I don’t know what the point of this is, if
we were— which is a little bit how you responded, right? Then they also— Often
they want to object to multiple premises at the same time. They want to object
to all the premises, for example. And they’ll tell them, No, you’re not
allowed to do that; yeah, there are rules for how we do this, right?
And
those rules are, here’s one important rule: You’re not allowed to object to
the conclusion. You have to tell that to the students. They’re like, I think
the conclusion’s false. I’m like, No no no! You’ve got to show me, right?
Because I did this thing, you can’t just object that the conclusion is false.
That’s not, you can’t— That’s not in the space of responses, right? And you
can’t object to more than one premise at a time. You can say that there’s a
fallacy of equivocation or something like that. So you can say that the
argument is invalid, the conclusion doesn’t follow, but that’s different from
objecting.
Okay. So I’ve given you an argument with some premises. And
now the thing that you were just saying was maybe—though you didn’t quite
phrase it this way—an objection to one of the premises. We could phrase it
that way. Namely, one of the premises of this argument was that little girls
are the experts in pink and purple. And you might think, Well, I have an
argument to the effect that they’re not, namely, there’s a way that expertise
usually works.
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
Okay. The way that it usually works, people don’t tend to like lose it or
become less expert over time. And that indicates that little girls are not, in
fact, the experts in prettiness. Right?
Robin:
Okay.
Agnes:
Okay. So that move is permissible within this game that we’re playing,
but—except that—in addition to presenting that premise of little girls being
specialists— I actually give you a mini argument for them being the
specialists, right? And when you get an argument for a premise, then you’re—
then the premise itself is kind of a conclusion, right? And then you’re not
just allowed to object to the to the premise.
My little argument was,
Well, think of who is the population that is sort of, you know, exclusively
concerned with pretty things: That is, they’re only concerned with pretty
things, that pretty things are the only things that they’re concerned with.
And I listed some pretty things.
Robin:
So you’re postulating some sort of natural decay with limited attention. Like
little girls are paying more attention to prettiness. And later on they get
distracted with other things. And so their expertise of prettiness would
naturally decline with their distractions.
Agnes:
Well, so now you’re— you’ve noticed something here, right? So you’ve noticed
this is a weird kind of expertise. And now you want me to explain how this
happens, and I’m happy to try to do that. But if I were teaching— if this were
a class, I would teach and I would say, You’re going off on a tangent.
Right?
We can try to like explore that question later, if you want this
question of, How does this funny kind of expert come into being? And maybe we
should—I think it is an interesting question. But that’s irrelevant to the
argument that I just gave you. Maybe you just accept the argument. Right?
Maybe you think I’m right? And then we can move on to that question.
Robin:
I think I sort of just misconceived the whole framing of the discussion, which
maybe I’m learning. But like I wasn’t primarily concerned with evaluating
whether you had made a valid argument.
Agnes:
Valid incentive, right? I— that is, I mean, yeah: The premises have to be true
and the conclusion has to follow.
Robin:
I was more trying to find a way to sort of engage what you said and to connect
it to things I think, and try to wonder like can I— can we talk productively
about this topic? So I’m looking for a broader framework to share. And that’s
the thing I was worried I don’t have…
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
…when you have this word pretty, that I’m not quite sure what it means.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
So I was going to make the comment that I think actually one of the most
important intellectual skills—especially for people who like to think in
abstractions, like you and do—is to choose the right level of abstraction at
the right moment in a conversation or analysis. So I think the most powerful
thinkers are really good at taking concrete examples and then jumping to
abstractions, and then jumping back down to concrete examples, and back and
forth. So that they sort of get the most out of their inference and then their
reasoning.
And so, you know, there’s a common observation that’s a
complaint by some sort of intellectuals, that they have just gotten so
abstract that they don’t really know what their words mean, and they’ve lost
any grounding, and they just like keep— they’ve got— They’ve agreed on some
rules about how these words are used in their debates, and then they just go
on, but they just, you know, the rest of us can’t figure out what they’re
saying or why it would be valuable because they just won’t connect their
abstract words to concrete things we understand.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
And so I think that does happen sometimes, and I’ve seen it happen sometimes.
And so that’s why— So here, you know, I like talking with you abstractly. We
talk about many abstract things. But here I was feeling like this is getting
too abstract in the sense that, you know, this word prettiness: I don’t know
what it means.
Agnes:
I believe this is our least abstract discussion that we had. So let me say, so
first of all I think “pretty” is like not a very abstract concept. That is,
many of the words we use are not— like “norm”, right? We use that — you and I
use that word all the time. Most ordinary people don’t use that word so much.
And I gave a list, right? Rainbows, unicorns, flowers, fairies, princesses,
dresses, right? So it’s like a pretty concrete list of things that are pretty.
Robin:
Oh, those are things that girls like! But whether they are “pretty”…
Agnes:
Oh, so we can go back to the argument, right? And you can say, Look, your
second premise, right, into— in effect contains an argument, and I don’t think
those things are pretty, those are just things little girls think are pretty.
That’s a fair response.
Robin:
They are pretty in some senses.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
And the question is like, Which senses do we want to talk about here?
Agnes:
Okay. Maybe it would help me, like, what— give me another sense of pretty.
Like what are some things that are— that you think of as pretty but that don’t
fit this mold?
Robin:
So if I was trying to say what does “pretty” mean…
Agnes:
Mm-hm.
Robin:
…first I would— you know, it would be comfortable. So that like things that
are threatening are not pretty.
Agnes:
Okay, comfortable.
Robin:
That would be an essence. It would also have to be like, attractive. Like it
would draw you toward it. But that’s why I might add the “comfortable,” right?
So hideous things might draw you toward them—
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
—you might, can’t look away from something hideous, but you wouldn’t call it
pretty. So there’d have to be like an attraction without that matching
repulsion.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
Right? And then it would have to sort of be foreground and background. Right?
So you can be in a pleasant environment, but you won’t call it pretty unless
you’re directed to pay attention directly to it. Otherwise it will just be a
nice background. Right? But if— even in a park, you could walk along in the
park and then not be looking at the park, just enjoying the experience. When
you say the park it’s pretty, that immediately calls whoever you’re talking to
to look at the park directly and like ask themselves, When I look directly at
the park, does it seem pretty?
Agnes:
And so Imagine you’re in a park right now, okay? And it’s an extraordinarily
pretty park, but you’re going to attend to some of the most pretty— some of
the most paradigmatically pretty things in it, what would those things be?
Robin:
Well so these would be things that are attractive and not hideous, and that
call your attention. So they would tend to be colors, for example…
Agnes:
Okay, colors, yeah? What else? I mean—
Robin:
There would be textures. There would be contrasts—
Agnes:
You mean textures can be pretty? Wouldn’t it be things?
Robin:
A mixture of— A nice mixture of textures. So the bark of the tree, the smooth
of the leaf, the ripple of the water: The mixture of textures would be pretty.
Agnes:
The bark of a tree is pretty?
Robin:
In the context of the other textures, yes.
Agnes:
So I tend to think of pretty as applying first and foremost not to, like, not
to textures but to things, right? And then—
Robin:
I would say a scene is pretty. So I wouldn’t necessarily— I could pick a
butterfly or a flower as things in the— if I had to pick something that was
pretty.
Agnes:
Okay, if you had to pick something you’d pick butterfly and flower: That’s
exactly what little girls would pick. Those are the two things they would
pick, butterflies and flowers. If you look at little girls’ dresses, they’re
covered in butterflies and flowers. So still, for you, good little girls. At
least as far as which things.
Robin:
Well, but you made me pick a thing. But I would first say the whole scene was
pretty.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
I would be less likely— I mean I might pick a particular flower and say,
That’s an especially pretty flower.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
And the flower would have a mixture of colors and textures.
Agnes:
Sure.
Robin:
And you know, shading and shape. And it would be pleasant, it wouldn’t be
hideous, right? I would, you know, I could see a mixture of colors in a bird
whose head had been torn off, but that won’t be pretty.
Agnes:
Right, right. Even though, I mean—
Robin:
It could striking—
Agnes:
It could be striking.
Robin:
… and it could be [extra resonating], and make me pay attention to it.
Agnes:
Why couldn’t it be pretty? I mean, that is, it wouldn’t be comfortable. But
why wouldn’t it be comfortable? It’s not gonna attack you. The head’s been
torn off.
Robin:
But still, it has— it brings out these associations that are uncomfortable.
Agnes:
Okay, good. So it has to have like no uncomfortable associations.
Robin:
Reduced.
Agnes:
Reduced uncomfortable associations, right, which makes sense with the rainbow,
flower, unicorn, fairies… butterflies.
Robin:
But I mean, there is going to be an element of what I would call “spice.” So
if you’re in a say, pleasant park-like environment over and over and day after
day, you will become like used to it. And then something is pretty that will
stand out relative to that, even if it isn’t like as fundamentally pretty,
perhaps, just taken by itself and without comparing it to other things, right?
Agnes:
Right. So it has to grab your attention.
Robin:
Right. And so for— it has to be different, and that will compromise on some of
these other things, right? And that’s in some sense, you know, I would think—
If I’m thinking of like, What’s the main ways people could disagree about what
counts is pretty? That would certainly be one of them. That is, I think most
adults who would criticize a child’s choice of pretty would be complaining
that it’s just too easy and obvious and standard, and a kind of pretty that
they’ve gotten tired of. And they will want spice, they will want something
that stands out as a bit different than pretty. Right?
Agnes:
And yet when asked for your paradigmatic examples of which things count as
pretty, you gave the same— you didn’t give some new adult version.
Robin:
Right?
Agnes:
You didn’t say like lion, or something more, you know—
Robin:
Right. Because I haven’t actually walked in a park with a lot of colorful
flowers lately, and it would be fresh and new for me at the moment.
Agnes:
Okay…
Robin:
But here I am in an office building.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
And so, you know, if I had walked all my life in an office— in the park, and
if I had been a forager or, you know, and walked all my life in the woods, and
I finally came across this building I’m in right now and I’ve never seen a
building like this, this would be pretty.
Agnes:
Do you— I mean, so you— It must be that sometimes in your life, you’ve
encountered very novel forms of architecture that you hadn’t experienced.
Robin:
Right. Or a street full of them.
Agnes:
But like in most of those cases, when I think about my own cases, even ones
that I really liked, they don’t strike me as pretty. That’s not the word that
I would use.
Robin:
And you just may have a better sense in your mind of what the word pretty
should go with—it’s not a word I use a lot. And so that’s part of what’s going
on here is I just have to ask—
Agnes:
Right, and so maybe you’re not the group. But see, little girls use the word a
lot.
Robin:
But so if I want to know what people who use the word a lot mean by it, then,
you know, it follows if I just want to say, Well, what’s the most common usage
of the word by the people who use the word most? Sure. But then…
Agnes:
But I mean, if you— If there’s, with respect to a given concept, say, there’s
a group of people who use the word a lot, it plays an important role in their
lives, they make a lot of decisions on the basis of it, etc.—like normally
those criteria are sufficient for us to say these are the specialists. So what
is it that the little girls are lacking?
Robin:
I think I and most people, and maybe even you, are just more careful and
cautious when like values are at play.
Agnes:
Uh-huh.
Robin:
And “pretty” evokes status, so “pretty” is a value judgment. It’s seen as
value judgment. And so when you’re saying something’s pretty, you are saying
that it’s more valuable.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
And you know, I have learned that people are more sensitive about value
judgments, and they want you to be more careful with them. And so I try harder
to sort of not make assumptions too easily about value judgments that might,
for example, offend somebody, or make them feel unvalued. And so that’s why I
would be especially careful with, you know, agreeing to a claim that includes
a word that’s a value judgment, especially if I’m not so sure I know what the
word means.
Agnes:
So you’re kind of just wary of this argument.
Robin:
I’m being defensive.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
Yes, defensive about just the conclusion itself, right?
Agnes:
Okay, but this is interesting, right? If you think about it you might— You, in
the beginning you were inclined to think this is kind of a trivial thing.
Right? Unimportant. But actually you’re afraid of this argument and wary about
it, right?
Robin:
Well it’s both, I mean that both that it’s—
Agnes:
Yeah.
Robin:
Right, you can have an important topic but still not see like what you’re
going to gain about talking about it.
Agnes:
Uh-huh.
Robin:
And so you both want the topic to sort of be a thing that matters in some
absolute cosmic sense, and then you want there to be reason why you should
talk about it now. What you’re going to do with it, what you could do with it.
Right? So for example, you know, many people want to have an answer to “Is
there a God?” And some of us want to know, What do you mean by a God? before
we answer the question, right? Before we get into that. Because there are all
these different concepts of God, and maybe our opinion about whether there’s a
God depends on which kind of god you’re talking about.
And sometimes
people, they don’t want to make a decision, they just want to have an opinion
on whether there’s a God and it’s somehow important just to have that word.
They want to have the word “I believe in God,” and then they’re often quite
lawyerly about coming up with a definition of God that will allow them to say
they believe in God. Even though I might think, Well that’s not what most
people mean by God, but they wanted to believe in God.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
And so that makes me wary about these situations where people have these big
words and they like seem to like focus on a pretty basic but value-laden claim
about a pretty abstract term that I’m not sure what it means.
Agnes:
So I mean, let’s take, you know, if we take our previous conversation which
was about the criminal justice system, I believe that I am never going to be
in a position where I would be reforming the criminal justice system. And I
don’t believe like, you know, what I think about it is really going to have
much impact on anything else. I can be wrong about that, but that’s my advice.
So do you think like, there it would make sense for me to have responded to
you similarly, “I just— I don’t know why we’re talking about this topic.”
Robin:
And then I would have had a set of responses to that. Yeah, I mean that’s a
completely valid point to bring up. And if I don’t give an adequate response
to it then it’s a point at which it’s valid to stop thinking about the topic.
Absolutely. But I think I would have reasonable responses there. But you know,
I might not convince you.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
So I do think like in general we have this risk of becoming too abstract in
our discussion. And it’s a risk because if you move to higher-level
abstractions, like the sentences are shorter, the chains of inference are
shorter. People can, you know, at least summarize you more quickly. It’s very
tempting to just move to very high-level abstractions and to say, you know,
God is good, good things exist, therefore God exists; you know, little games
like that, right?
And, but if there’s a risk that like you’re just being
really too sloppy at those abstractions and, you know, it doesn’t actually
follow, then you want to push yourself to be a little more concrete. So you
can like be sure you’re being careful. And so then the question is, How do you
judge that?
And so I think one of the things we do is the concept of
actionable, and I just think it’s a concept that academics don’t use quite as
much as they should. You want to like look for a decision nearby that
potentially you could make such that this would bear on that decision. And
even if that’s not such an important decision, just the exercise of connecting
what you say to a decision that would be actual makes things much more
concrete in many ways that will be then— help to clarify what you’re talking
about.
Agnes:
Yeah. So I think— I mean on the one hand I think this is very actionable for
you in that like you could just decide to incorporate more pink and purple
into your life, like you could decorate, your office could become purple,
etc., because you want to be prettier. And maybe you would then think also
you’ll become more attuned to this distinctive form of value. (We can talk
about the value bit in a minute.)
And that seems actually easier to me to
imagine that that will be a— This seems to be a very concrete question
actually, very not-abstract, the argument that I gave. But I want to hear, how
is the criminal justice question actionable for me, what can I do?
Robin:
Well, you know, most social reform, you know, doesn’t just happen by, you
know, experts talking to experts and convincing experts to do things
different. Living in a democracy, we typically need some recruiting of a wider
circle, at least of elites, and even wider publics to support an idea or at
least not oppose it.
And so quite commonly discussion of social reform
considers like larger perceptions of things and tries to recruit conversations
by other people to support, or at least not oppose, the reforms. So very few
people make very technical, detailed reforms that are like only listened to by
experts, right? So at least on something this big, clearly we would never make
a change this big without a lot of ordinary people like thinking a bit about
it and having a reaction.
Agnes:
So you’ve answered the question as to why it would be in your interest to talk
to me about this topic: Namely, you’ve got to convince quite a lot of people
to change their minds in order to possibly bring about your reform. But you
haven’t answered the question, What’s in it for me? Given that I’m going into
this thinking, This reform sounds kind of crazy…
Now, I’m happy to talk
to you about it nonetheless, right? But I’m now wondering, suppose that I had
adopted the framing of I’m only willing to talk to Robin about this if I can
see some thing actionable here, right? I don’t know what would have shown up
for me that way.
Robin:
Well for the purpose of clarifying concepts, it’s less important that it’s
personally actionable than it’s actionable by somebody, somehow.
Agnes:
Uh huh.
Robin:
Right? So you know, maybe you don’t drive a car, right? But we could still
talk about actions related to a car if we were thinking ambiguously about
traffic, or thinking about the design of roads or something like that. And we
were talking about like straightness of roads. Then I might, you know, ground
that out into sort of how easy is it to follow the road as a driver? And then
that might make it clear what I meant by the straightness of a road. And then
the fact that you don’t personally drive cars wouldn’t be that big a criticism
of using that example to clarify what we meant.
Agnes:
So I mean, the— I think the standard view about colors is that, you know—and I
don’t know, because I don’t hear this topic discussed so much; people are not
very willing to talk about colors, in fact—but the standard view might be
there’s no such thing as a prettier or less pretty color, all the colors are
equally pretty. That— I think that standard view is wrong. I think some colors
are especially ugly—like sort of beigey, kind of vomity type colors? And then
I think, you know, pink and purple are especially pretty, right? If my view
came to be sort of dominant in the world like that there are— that there’s
this, now, you know, spectrum of colors in terms of prettiness, right? Your
thought is you can’t imagine any way that that would be actionable?
Robin:
I would turn around and say, If you gave that to me as the context for your
question I would have a lot more to work with in thinking about what the
answer to your question is. I would then know more what you meant by the words
because you have given me that hypothetical as the framing of the question.
Agnes:
You mean the one where everyone comes around to the view that I have?
Robin:
Or even that it becomes accepted— widely accepted. That it is, you know,
pretty colors or whatever.
Agnes:
Okay. I mean, so let’s go back to the question about you don’t like that it’s
a value judgment, you don’t want to step on people’s toes. So you know,
aesthetic value is a kind of value, right?
Robin:
Right.
Agnes:
And there are like fine-grained words for aesthetic value. That is, we don’t
only have like the phrase “aesthetic value,” right? We have, in different
domains, words for, you know, I don’t know, if somebody’s playing the music
was like very tight, or very expressive, or— right? And those are value terms,
right, in that—
Robin:
They move in the direction of being more technical. That is, you know, if you
have like, a piece of music has a little marking about whether to play it fast
or slow, right? And you could say whether this piece of music was played fast
or slow, right?
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
And in some sense that’s a non-value judgment. It can be used that way because
you just mean to say it, like, it varies on context whether it should be
played fast or slow. But in a context you might be complaining that it’s too
slow, and it might be understood in that context that this sort of thing
should be played fast, and that it therefore was a complaint to say that it
was slow. But in that sense it wouldn’t be a value judgment, right?
Agnes:
Right. But there also— I don’t know if you ever heard it— So you know, I have
a number of like music lovers and musicians in my family, that they will often
speak of a particular performance, like maybe it wasn’t note-perfect, but it
was very— had a lot of musicality,
Robin:
Okay.
Agnes:
I have no idea what they’re talking about, but I sort of trust them to there
is this thing, musicality, it’s a distinctive form of value. They are kind of
the experts in this domain because they talk about music all the time, they
listen to it, it’s like a big important part of their lives. And so in effect
I sort of credit them with these value terms that are terms of aesthetic
value. So it’s not just a question of how fast or how slow, but distinctive
aesthetic forms of value. And so that’s what I’m claiming there is for pretty.
Robin:
And if they want me to endorse a claim about musicality with this particular
piece of music, then I would feel more of a problem if I didn’t know what they
meant by musicality. So that’s— If I can see different communities and people
using that term differently—or at least apparently using it differently, maybe
there’s a unified concept behind it that I don’t see—but if they want me to
endorse or not a claim about musicality, that seems like they’re trying to
like recruit me in their value dispute.
Agnes:
But suppose that— So I hadn’t put forward any kind of just— I mean now I sort
of did, slightly about the— Mostly I think it’s people don’t think about this,
not that there’s some big dispute. But with the musicality, you know, suppose
you had a bunch of musical people in your family, right? And those musical
people are all like, Oh, you know, Glenn Gould plays with such musicality,
right? Whatever that means.
Like now if another group comes along with—
where they equally tend to use the word “musicality” all the time and they’re
just very into music, and they’re like, No, he has no musicality—then you
might be confused, right? But suppose that no such competition has come along
yet, right? All the people you’ve ever encountered for whom this is a big deal
all say, like about certain people and certain performances, there’s like a
lot of consensus, right? Like there is about Glenn Gould, right? And that I’m
at least inclined to be like, Okay, I guess, you know? I mean, like…
Robin:
There’s probably another thing going on here that I should just acknowledge
which might seem silly, but I think it’s important: Like when somebody, say,
starts a podcast, and they say, This is my claim—
Agnes:
Yeah.
Robin:
I think you’re just more generally wondering all the different ways that
claimed inference could go wrong, right?
Agnes:
Mm.
Robin:
Whereas if you had sort of asked for my assent indirectly, in the context of
some other conversation, I might easily have granted it. But if you hang it
out as the central claim, you know, and a lot of focus is going onto it, I
mean, they’ll go, Well, like what’s the trick in this one? Why is this
anything other than what it seems? Because if it was just what it seems you
might think, Well, then it wouldn’t be this central and it wouldn’t be getting
highlighted attention.
Agnes:
I see. So like, I mean… But then it’s not, it’s— This claim is not
extraordinary. It’s just in every podcast that you’re on, if somebody makes a
claim…
Robin:
What if somebody makes a claim and you’re not sure what they mean by it?
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
And then they wonder whether you agree. Then, you know, if it’s going to be
the central point of the discussion and you’re not sure what they mean, then
it seems appropriate to like first dig into what they might mean by it before
you decide whether you agree or not.
Agnes:
I’m just skeptical about your claim that you don’t know what I mean here. That
is it seems to me you’re quite a competent user of the word “pretty.” And when
asked to identify pretty things, you identified some of the same things that I
did. And your list of traits, right? Where it’s supposed to be sort of
comfortable and attractive—
Robin:
So then you and I agree on that, and then realized that we don’t disagree on
what’s pretty. But like, I can’t be confident of that until we go through that
exercise.
Agnes:
Okay, but so now that we’ve gone through that exercise, are there any of the—
Let me repeat the argument so you can remember what the premises were, so you
can tell me if you disagree with any of the premises. Okay? So the first
premise is that specialists in any domain, like in a domain x, are best at
discerning what is x-ish? And maybe let me—
Robin:
You don’t mean to say “tends to”? You mean to say “are best”?
Agnes:
Tend to be best. I’m fine with tends. Tends to be best at discerning what is
x-ish, right? Other things equal.
Robin:
Okay.
Agnes:
And maybe there are special cases that we can go into, right? And let me add
something to that premise. (That’s our first premise.) Like you know, this is
also true of domains of aesthetic value, okay? So x can be a domain of
aesthetic value. And then the second claim is that little girls are
specialists in prettiness, for which I had a sub-argument that they’re into
all and only pretty things. And then the third premise is that little girls
prefer pink and purple to other colors and see them as prettier. And so then I
have my conclusion that pink and purple are the prettiest colors.
Okay.
So now that you feel we have a shared sense of what these words mean, do you
object to any of the premises, or do you think that the conclusion fails to
follow from the premises? That’s the other move available to you.
Robin:
So because, you know, first of all I don’t actually know that little girls
like pink and purple more than other people, but will just take that for a
given…
Agnes:
And I admit that that’s just my own— going from my own sort of like personal
experience, and it may have changed culturally since.
Robin:
It could easily be answered by just walking into a clothing store targeted at
these little girls and looking at the colors of the clothes.
Agnes:
Yes.
Robin:
And the girls have the freedom to choose the clothes, and the marketers are
trying to target them, then if I see a lot of pink and purple then I would
say, Okay, looks like little girls like pink and purple.
Agnes:
Yes.
Robin:
I could be easily convinced in that way.
Agnes:
Yes. And it’s not all, like, it’s just by and large, right? So yeah.
Robin:
I could even— We can even go to a website now, like, and look at a website for
little girls and say, you know, type in “little girl dresses,” and see the
colors of the pictures that come up, right?
Agnes:
Okay. Yes, that’s true. Right. But so, like for, you know, and— Our listeners
at home can do that while they’re listening to us, and tell us whether we’re
right or not—whether I’m right about that. But so, right, so that’s a
potential objection to the third premise, right? That little girls prefer pink
and purple to other colors.
Robin:
I think that the hardest one is the idea that they specialize in pretty. Like—
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
Like, we might say they like the word “pretty.”
Agnes:
Yeah.
Robin:
Right? But we might think that girls using the word “pretty” among themselves
would be a different usage, say, than adults might have with the word “pretty”
among themselves. We might not be sure it’s the same word, the same usage of
the word.
Agnes:
Right. I mean, I think it’s not just that they, like, they use the word. They
would also, for instance if they’re drawing pictures, they would tend to draw
pictures of pretty things. Right? They would tend to— When I was maybe—
Robin:
Well, they will draw pictures of things they like, and they might use the word
“pretty” for that. And do we mean the word “pretty” by that?
Agnes:
I mean they’re going to be pictures of flowers and butterflies. Those were
your examples of pretty things. So I think that they’re what you mean by
pretty.
Robin:
I mean, they are pretty to some— I mean, but again, so I imagine like in the
background is somebody who disagrees with this claim, right?
Agnes:
It’s you, apparently!
Robin:
Well, I’m just perhaps reluctant to endorse it. I don’t necessarily disagree.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
And I haven’t like disagreed with the claim, I’m just like, if you ask for my
endorsement of the claim, and then I pause and I go like, What’s at stake
here? And like… So, it—
Agnes:
I’m not actually asking for your endorsement. Actually, it’s not how we do
philosophy. I’m actually asking for you to argue against it. I want you to
argue against it. That’s what I seek. If you just endorse it that would be
boring.
Robin:
So I mean, I think I made this point before, but I mean I guess I want to be
clear, like, that in my world of experience making value claims is more
controversial, and gets you into more trouble and more people are turned off,
or put off, by trying to make value claims in arguments. And so I’m in the
habit of, when possible, like turning a discussion into a discussion about
something else if I can reach the same end in those other terms.
So we
economists even have the standard practice of taking values as given by this;
we assume that people value what they value, we’re not going to argue with
them about their values, but we’re going to try to show them how to get more
of their values through various institutional-decision choices. Right? And so
that’s a concrete example of how we are wary.
And I think that’s also
true: Like if you go to a restaurant, the waiter might try to advise you to—
some of the dishes are good, right? And you know, if they say the broccoli
fettuccine is especially good tonight, and you say, But I don’t like broccoli,
they don’t then try to argue you out of the broccoli, right? They tend to
think like they should find what you like, and then with respect to that give
you an argument about why a particular dish would be the good dish for you,
given your values. Even waiters and restaurants are reluctant to sort of try
to directly change your values through argument, right?
There’s an
example, I think, much more widely of advisors of all sorts tend to be wary of
trying to tell you should change your values, and more— I mean, even at a
dress store or something. Right? If they say, This looks like a really pretty
dress, what do you think? And you say, you know, I don’t like pink and purple,
they’re not going to bring the argument up and try to convince the person to
like pink and purple. They’re going to find whatever colors they do think they
like and try to give them things like that.
Agnes:
I mean I probably have more experience with people advising, re: dresses in
dress stores, than you. So I can tell you that they do give you advice, and
they will contravene you by saying like for instance that something that you
think doesn’t look good on you, they might be like, It looks good on you.
Now
some of these people are not trustworthy and they’ll just tell you that
everything looks good on you. But a lot of these people know that if they do
that, you’re suspicious. And so they might actually, like, you know—
Robin:
Randomly tell you a few things are bad…
Agnes:
Or honestly tell you! The good ones will be honest. Right? But they— and
they’ll try to convince you. They’ll be like, Look, you think this looks good
on you, but it doesn’t. You think it doesn’t look good on you, but it does.
And they might get, you know, revert to features of it.
Similarly, with
the broccoli, the guy might be like, Well, you know, you may have tried only
ever steamed or boiled broccoli, but have you ever had oven-roasted broccoli
rabe, or something? You know, it’s really quite special. It’s different than
what you expect. I mean, I think people argue in these contexts all the time.
Robin:
But I still think it’s held to a higher standard. So I still think you need to
be a more trusted advisor, and a higher-status advisor, in order to be able to
make the value-advising move. And so the more that you are suspect as an
advisor, or are not trusted, not high-status, then the more you will try to
advise in terms of…
So for example if you have an auto repair person, you
might trust them for the purpose of getting your car repaired. But if they
want to suggest a new color fender or a new artistic feature to the car, you
might say to yourself, you’re an auto repair person, not a car decorator, and
I’m not going to listen to you about decoration advice. Because you have
classified them as somebody who does not have good, you know, advice or
knowledge about this artistic thing they’re trying to recommend about the car.
Agnes:
Right. But like, if they did have that, you know, then— So I mean, is it
basically like economists have kind of relegated themselves to being
low-status and not trusted? And so they’re only going to advise in these
domains that are, you know, kind of appropriate for their station or
something? But maybe philosophers are like higher up, they’re either higher
status or more trusted or both, and so we feel comfortable arguing about
values?
Robin:
In fact most people don’t really trust philosophers that much about values
either.
Agnes:
Then why do we feel so comfortable? Like—
Robin:
Because it’s, you picked your thing, right?
Agnes:
Uh huh.
Robin:
So you know, all of these things are basically a coordination game of a
profession or an area trying to sort of create a habit of what they do, and a
brand about what they do, so that they can present that brand to the world and
like sort of reliably meet the brand promise. And you know, find people
continuing to want to come back to them. So certainly the economics brand is
not about advising on values.
The philosophy brand is more about advising
on values, but in some sense that’s part of why, like, philosophers aren’t in,
you know, presidential board meetings so often, right? It is in fact the
economists’ reputation for being, you know— A neutral advisor will help you
achieve your values, that gives the economists more entree into, you know,
corporate board meetings, into policy-wonk discussions, into, you know,
Congressional advisories. That’s part of what it does.
Agnes:
You can have more influence if you’ve relegated yourself to allowing yourself
to be used to someone else’s ends. Like you’re— In effect you make your mind
into a tool that someone else can in effect better achieve their goals using.
Is that—
Robin:
Well, I mean all advisors are trying to help the advisee, right? So for all
advisors you need to create the impression in the advisee that the advisee
will be helped, right? So that that’s just generically true for advisors—if
the advisee does not believe that you will be helpful then you have lost, you
know, their trust or interest in you as an advisor. So that doesn’t
necessarily make you, you know, only a slave to their interest. But it means
you had to convince them that you would further their interest sufficiently in
order for them to select you as an advisor.
Agnes:
Right. But there’s— One question is like, Why would you want to advise them?
Like why would you want to advise the president? Why would you want to advise—
whatever. And one reason is it might be that like you share some of their
goals, right, and you want those goals to be achieved. Maybe you don’t share
all their goals, right, only some.
Now, if you only share some of their
goals, I guess you have to sort of trick them into thinking that you share
more— Like because you might be pushing, in effect, your agenda, right? Or you
might just really like advising people. Like you just might want to be
influential, that might be good enough for you. And so you’re willing to
advise them how to achieve their goals, so long as you can be sort of useful
to them. That’s good enough for you, right?
Robin:
Well, if I imagine myself as different kinds of advisors and economists, then
I might think up different answers to the question. But I’m used to being an
economist. So I’m used to the answer that I give as an economist, which may
not generalize very well to other kinds of roles.
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
But we economists have this framing where we like describe different people as
having preferences and things they want, and then we think about institutions
that would help all of them get more of what they want. And that we try to
present ourselves as people who just follow that system consistently, just—
There’s a general system of giving people generically what they want, whatever
it is they want. And our system doesn’t very much depend on what particular
thing they want. It’s just a general way to give them more of whatever it is
they want.
And that— Working at that level of abstraction we can, you
know, basically promise people that we will in general find potential deals
for you to make that will give all of the people involved in this deal more of
whatever it is they want, and that our strategies are not very tuned toward
what we want, or in particular things you might want—they’re more generically
to give you all whatever it is you want.
Agnes:
Why do you want to give other people whatever it is they want, irrespective of
what they want?
Robin:
So I mean, that’s a sort of way in which we, in common with many philosophers
even, frame our prosociality. We think that yes, in general, if I help you get
what you want, and you help me get what I want, then we together get more of
what we want, and then we are all better off, and I approve of that. That is,
I approve of people making deals together to get more of what they want,
because then they all get whatever, and then it just looks good for everybody.
Agnes:
So like, you know, if the economist is advising the president or whatever and
they’re helping other people get what they want, it’s because they think that
they’ll get more stuff? They, the advisor, the economist, will also be getting
stuff out of that? More of what they want, which might be independent—
Robin:
Right, but this is a standard business question, right? And I could be— If
people say, What’s the secret to riches in business? Well, you know a common
thing, which is quite correct, is find a way to give value to people. Find a
way that you can give more value to them than they’re getting out of their
competitors, and that’s the secret to riches in business. Right?
First
ask, What do your customers want? What aren’t they getting that they want? Can
you find a way to give that to them? And if you can find a way to give your
customers something they want that they aren’t getting from other people, then
they will like you, and they will want to do business with you. And that’s how
you get rich.
Agnes:
So, like—
Robin:
You can make the same argument for economists, right? To be a valued advisor
you have to be giving value to the people you’re advising, and the more you
give them value the more they will value your advice. And you can both get
rich in some sense and be doing good for the world.
Agnes:
And like when I give advice, you know, it’s mostly in the context of students.
When I give advice it’s mostly to undergraduate students, right? And they
might want to know things like, you know, How should I learn ancient Greek?
Right?—and this is maybe a student who’s been in one of my classes—And should
I take a summer class? Should I try to take a regular class? Do I even need to
learn Greek?
You know, do I— Should I go to graduate school? Should I,
you know— Lots of questions like that. The students who I know, right, and I
try to help them talk through the situation. And I don’t think that I do that
with a view to what I’m going to be getting out of this. Like that they will
then as a result like give me something as a…
Robin:
Not directly. But could you just be trying to help them from their point of
view?
Agnes:
Sure. I mean I think of their goals as good, right? And so I don’t want to
help them get everything that they want. Like quite often they’ll come to me
with a set of things that they want, and I’ll say of some of those things, I
don’t that those things are very good, you shouldn’t be— Go for those ones.
Here’s how to get the other ones, though. Those ones are good, right? I feel
perfectly comfortable saying that.
And I mean, I wouldn’t say here’s how
to get it, because it’s hard to get it. But here’s some thoughts, and here’s
some thoughts on why those those other ones that you want aren’t so good. And
so like I feel it would be very weird for me to approach a student who wants a
set of things, and some of the wants I might think are misguided, but to in
some sense shield that from my judgment of its being misguided, and just tell
them how to get anything that is that they want, I guess then I would want
something back
Robin:
You are shielding it as long as you make it— the conditionality clear enough,
right? As long as you say, Well, for the things you want, these would be the
right mechanisms. But for these other things I think you should want, you
might consider focusing more on this. As long as they can separate out like
how to correct for what you want from them from what they want, then they
don’t mind this little sermon once in a while on what they should want.
Agnes:
Yeah, but I don’t see what incentive I would have for saying the first thing
at all. Like, I— Why would I tell someone how to get things that I don’t think
they should be getting?
Robin:
I mean, the most usual thing is just, almost everything everybody wants is
okay, it’s just about the weighting of them. So almost all disagreements about
value are usually like just how— about the relative importance of different
things. And so almost all the things that they want, you’ll agree aren’t
terrible things to want. You’ll just might not think that they should get the
priority they’re putting on them. And so that’s really where the disagreement
comes, about the right priority to put things.
Agnes:
Right. But I’m happy to talk about that too, and what they should be
prioritizing.
Robin:
Right. So there’s not so much a risk of them, like, getting bad things. It’s
the risk of getting too much of the wrong good things.
Agnes:
Right. I mean like, here’s the situation: Students are often coming to me, How
can I manage to fit in a double major or triple major. Okay, and many times my
thought is, Don’t major in so many things, you know? Pick one thing, major in
that thing, and you can still take classes in the other field. But there is an
illusion that you’re getting more credentialization by having more majors,
right?
And so I may be trying to persuade the student out of pursuing
this thing that they came to me for advice about how to get, right? But if I
saw myself as having to just give them advice—how to get your triple
major—like I would then want to know what are they paying me for this? Like I
want money or something, because I’m not achieving a good by just giving them
advice.
Robin:
Well you are— I mean, you have a job there, and this is part of your job. So
you can certainly just think that a certain degree of responsiveness to
students asking questions, that’s just part of your job.
Agnes:
Fair enough. Yes.
Robin:
And you shouldn’t like demand that they entertain you in particular with their
question before you answer it. I mean they might just think that you need to
put up with a bit of questioning even if it’s not so much fun for you, just
because it’s part of your job to answer their questions.
Agnes:
That’s true, but like I give advice to students who are not even University of
Chicago students, and I’m happy to do it. And high school students come to me.
But I would not feel fine with that if I’m giving them, you know…
Robin:
So there’s two levels here: We can say like you have a particular brand for
your style of answering questions which you’re describing here. It might not
be a very widely known brand. So many people who come to ask you might be just
reacting to sort of the overall average brand of, say, university professors,
and how they respond to advice.
And so there could be this question of,
What do we want, collectively, the brand of university professors’ advice to
be? And I would say that we—with respect to students—we are high-enough
status, and you know, know enough things relative to these key classroom value
choices, that they might well defer to us on those choices.
But if you
were to ask— if they were— you know, if you were to offer them advice about
who to date, or even where to eat, they might think you were moving past your
legitimate area that they would accept your advice for, but you still might
offer it.
But you know, large professional economics, you know, we have a
question: Are we just generic people that you can come ask for advice and
we’ll just tell you things? Or do we do— you know, how much of a brand have we
agreed on? We apparently have agreed on more of a brand where we separate out
the value part of our advice.
Agnes:
Okay, but I want to use— Since we’re, we just have like a little bit of time
left, I want to go back to our central question about the prettiest colors.
First of all, it just occurs to me that it’s possible that we want to add like
silver and gold. I think those figure largely in like that sphere as well.
Robin:
I picture white. I picture all of these things in the background with a lot of
white.
Agnes:
Yes. So you need the white to make them stand out.
Robin:
Yeah.
Agnes:
But it’s not one of the pretty colors. I mean, it’s one of the—
Robin:
Well, but it’s necessary for the prettiness!
Agnes:
It’s necessary, yes. But there’s a wonderful line in the Phaedo: Imagine not
being able to tell the difference between something’s being necessary for
something else and like the point of that thing, right? So like the example is
like, why Socrates—okay, so Socrates is in his a jail cell, he’s about to be
executed—you know, Why did you not run away? He was offered an opportunity to
pay the jailers and run off, and he’s like, Someone could say, Well, it’s my
bones that are, you know, like, are here.
And like, but he’s like, But
you know, these same bones could be off in some other country if I had decided
to do something else. So my bones are like a necessary condition of me being
here as opposed to somewhere else, but they don’t explain— The reason why I’m
not there is that I thought it was right to stay here. Right? So I think
similarly, white is a necessary condition for the prettiness of purple and
pink and silver and gold, but the thing that it exists for the sake of in that
context is going to be the pretty colors, and the pretty things that the
colors make up.
Robin:
So we have a language of preferences, you know, as I mentioned, economists
use.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
And we also have a language of values. And in some sense they’re redundant
languages, and that we can describe the same things using either language. And
that seems to be a key choice in using those two languages. And it seems to me
like the language of preferences is often a choice which has the subtext, “And
let’s not argue about values,” right?
If we just say, I like strawberry
and you like vanilla, and we call those preferences, part of that is to say,
Let’s just accept that we like different things here, and like go on from
there. Whereas if we call it, I have a fundamental value for strawberry, I’m
more making the move that I think you should share my value for strawberry.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
And that we need to have a discussion about this, if you seem to like vanilla.
Agnes:
Right.
Robin:
And that’s an interesting move.
Agnes:
Right. And as an economist, you don’t have a view about which move is better,
right? Because that’s itself a value claim, like whether it’s better to…
Robin:
Well it might be— One might be better for some other instrumental reason—
Agnes:
Okay.
Robin:
—and not a value reason, right?
Agnes:
Fair enough, fair enough! We’ve achieved our…
Robin:
And we can have a fundamental value preference over these two things, but it
wouldn’t be a value choice, right?
Agnes:
Okay, right.
Robin:
So we might ask just, Why do people make this move in the different ways they
do in various circumstances? That might give us a clue to sort of this
hesitancy I might have, and other people might have, to always make the value
move as opposed to the preference move, right? Sometimes— I mean it seems to
be on the surface that we use this preference language as a way to sort of
agree to disagree, if you like.
Agnes:
But I think in many contexts we do not use the preference language, and we use
the value language. I think when it comes to musical value, literary value,
etc., we are happy to say that, so to speak, the preferences of a group of
specialists dictate that domain of value. And I wonder whether the reason we
are not willing to do that here is just simple snobbery. Like we’re just not
willing to admit that the population that could be an expert in something
could be like young people.
Robin:
No, but we could turn it around and say, That observation may well be, you
know, valid, but what we say is, The context in which we want to go with value
descriptions rather than preference descriptions are exactly where there’s a
status rank, and we are going to show our status by having the proper values.
And we want to assert that we have high-status values. And therefore we want
to assert that we— It’s not just a matter of preference, it is a matter of
absolutes, and we are taking that stance. And that might be, exactly— explain
a lot of the variance in using preferences versus values as a label.
Agnes:
So I think a lot of like philosophers, the way they might view that what you
just said is like, Well, no, no, these are actual values, like the things
really are valuable, and we’re track— We may not— We may go wrong, right? But
we’re tracking it. Right? And I would sort of expect that the person who would
be in a bad position, the anti-specialist, for figuring out whether the value
language is tracking something distinctive or whether it’s simply a way of
like recapitulating status or something, the person who would be worse at that
would be the economist, right?
Because they’ve already gotten themselves
out of that game, right? They’re just inclined to flatten everything out in
terms of preferences. So that if you wanted someone to tell you, Look, is
there genuinely a domain of aesthetic value in which these little girls are
specialists? Or, No, these are just— little girls prefer pink and purple to
other colors, but that’s just one preference among many and other people might
prefer otherwise—You would not want to turn to an economist, right? You’d want
to turn to somebody who’d—
Robin:
I don’t think that's quite fair. So again we have these two different ways of
framing. We’re trying to ask which is the better way of framing—you can’t say
that one group who uses one way of framing therefore isn’t any good at
preparing these ways of framing if some of the other group is also just as
specialized in their way of framing, right? So if there’s a frame A and a
frame B, and some people almost always use A, and some people always use B,
and now our question is, What’s the better frame? If we go to the people who
always use A, they’re no better than the people who always use B.
Agnes:
I think that’s true. But I don’t— You yourself describe the economist as
saying that they want to put the values to the side, but I don’t accept the
description that philosophers want to put the pref— I want preferences and
values.
Robin:
But what is the difference then? I mean, you have—
Agnes:
Yeah, so I think that—
Robin:
It’s just a matter of convenient labeling, or like, what—
Agnes:
No, no. So I think a value— To value something is to be in a dispositional
state that is like a nexus of a set of attitudes. So one of them is desires or
preferences, right? So you have desires or preferences towards that thing.
Another is beliefs about the goodness of that thing—and articulately split up
the good of the thing—and the third is an emotional disposition to, for
instance, feel bad if the thing is threatened or whatever, right? And so you—
a valuational response is a coordinated cognitive, conative, and affective
response to something. So it’s not a mere preference.
Robin:
So, say I prefer strawberry. I believe that I prefer strawberry. I would be
sad if strawberry went away from the menu. That doesn’t qualify as a value to
get?
Agnes:
No, because believing that you— That’s not the relevant kind of belief. So the
kind of belief that I’m talking about is the belief that strawberry is good,
say.
Robin:
I do believe strawberry is good! But that’s not the same as saying I prefer
it.
Agnes:
And so like you might value straw— I mean, some people actually, I think, do
sort of get to that point, right? If there’s a certain level of attachment and
you’re like, No really, it’s the best flavor. And you know—
Robin:
But that just seems like the difference between… Basically, the key difference
between preferences and values is values is this claim that gets a universal
value and the preference is, it’s a per person value, right? It’s similar to
issues about whether morality is absolute or whether it’s relative to a
culture or a person, right? It’s about, you know, you have a predicate or
something, and just how many— how much context-dependence is allowed in it?
Right?
Agnes:
Well I think that’s part of it, but the definition I gave had three parts, and
I actually don’t think that universal bit is sufficient. I also think you need
the affective attachment. So that’s the emotional aspect of it. I think you
could imagine something where everybody believes that—
Robin:
Well people can easily have an effective attachment to preferences. That’s
very common.
Agnes:
Sure. I mean, sometimes they do—
Robin:
So that seems like the key difference here.
Agnes:
Sometimes they do, sometimes they don’t. I mean that is, you know, quite often
I might not get my preference in many ways, but I don’t— I do not feel
emotionally wounded. I don’t feel sad. I don’t feel angry.
Robin:
That just seems to mean it’s a big value, I would say, or a big preference,
right? Something that’s very small, you can’t be bothered to have an emotional
reaction. It all just passes quickly in the periphery of your vision and…
Agnes:
I mean sometimes I can have a small and quick emotional reaction to something.
So I mean, I guess I think maybe you’re using the word “big” now to mean what
I would say is like value, which is fine. But I do think that a value response
is a coordinated psychological response on a couple of different fronts.
Robin:
I might, you know, I might just say, People socially pay a lot of attention
to— So say there is only preferences, right? Then we could construct this idea
of value out of preferences. This is the kind of move an economist might make,
right? We might say, Well, people have preferences but they also do care about
how much they share preferences with other people, and that sometimes they
want to like make a commitment to a preference, and they even want to like
have a shared commitment to a preference.
And they might want to make
sure they know and see a shared commitment to a preference. And— especially if
it’s important to them. And so they might want to, for example, have ways they
check people to see if they share this preference or not, and to shame them if
they don’t, or praise them if they do. And it might just be important that
they share it.
So for example, in a law-abiding society we might think
some people around like to be criminal and violent. And we might want to know
if any one person we’re dealing with is such a person, they would not share a
preference for peace and politeness, but they have a preference for violence.
And then—
Agnes:
You as an economist would want to try to satisfy that preference, right,
insofar as it could be satisfied.
Robin:
You mean to be a person who doesn’t want violence?
Agnes:
No, one of the people that’s asking you for advice is the person who likes
violence. Right?
Robin:
Right. Sure.
Agnes:
You’d be trying to give them advice, how they can get more violence.
Robin:
Right. Yeah. But in this context, we’re just saying that like people might not
just have a preference for nonviolence, they might want to know who else
shares their preference for nonviolence, and then they might want to create a
process that would shame people and unveil them if they didn’t have this
desired, shared preference. And then they might feel emotional about this
shared preference they have, and threatened emotionally by people who might
violate it, or the prospect of that. That sounds a lot like a value. And I
might just say, That’s what a value means in the context of people who have
preferences.
Agnes:
Yeah, I mean I guess I think, you know, I can imagine… I think we could call
that a value. But then like some of those cases are going to be— So that
those, they’re going to include claims, like claims about goodness and stuff.
And those could be incorrect, right? So in some cases the person is making a
mistake, and they shouldn’t be doing any of that, right?
And so that’s
important like from my point of view about value, that it actually makes
claims that are truth-evaluable. Right? So you could imagine people
coordinating in just that way over slavery: Like how slavery is a good thing,
and I want to make sure— I want to coordinate with other people who—
Robin:
And those people would naturally speak of sharing the value of slavery. And…
Agnes:
Right, they would speak in that way. And so it’s possible to speak in all of
those ways, and to have all the framework, and to not see from the inside that
the thing that you take to be a value isn’t actually valuable. That’s like a
thing that could happen with values, whereas it’s different with preferences.
I don’t think— or it’s anyway rare to think it’s just—
Robin:
But that’s just about the predicate and how many arguments it has, really. I
mean again, you know, we could have all these same people having all these
same preferences, and they would act all the same except in one scenario, you
would say, But they have the wrong preference. In the other scenario you would
say they have the right preference. And so from their point of view,
explaining social behavior, whether it’s right or wrong, wouldn’t much affect
what they’re doing. It might affect your approval or not with what they’re
doing. But you know…
Agnes:
So I don’t really think it makes sense to speak of right and wrong
preferences, I guess. That is, as I see it, preference is like a motivational
condition. And it doesn’t make a claim—
Robin:
But in this translation, it would be—
Agnes:
But there could be ones that I don’t like, right? But I can imagine that
there’s people who don’t like the slavery thing—maybe they make less money if
there’s slavery than if there isn’t slavery, okay? And so they dislike it and
they try to change it or whatever. And that’s like one attitude, but a
different and distinct attitude that’s different from just, I’m only going to
make it go away because it’s disadvantaging me. It’s thinking it’s wrong or
incorrect.
Robin:
So I mean this is a common issue with morality, etc., you know, and we’re
about out of time here. But you know, just hold it up for next time, perhaps.
Agnes:
Yeah.
Robin:
You know, if we’re just trying to explain human behavior then we— It doesn’t
look like we ever need to know which things people want to do, or want, are
right or wrong or good or bad. We just need to know what they choose and what
they want. It’s only when we want to do this overall evaluation of what
they’re doing that we need to invoke this other concept. And many social
scientists, even myself, often wonder whether we even need this concept of
what’s really valuable in order to think ourselves about what we want to do
and what we want other people to do. It may be extraneous.
And similarly,
like in philosophy of mind where we say, Do we really need qualia evidence? Do
we really need sort of this extra consciousness thing that people often
invoke? We asked, What if we tried to do without that? You know, could we do
pretty much everything that you want to do without it? And you know, a common
intellectual attitude is often, you had a thing you thought was central, but
it figures—it turns out you can do without, maybe you should do without.
Agnes:
If I could have the last word—
Robin:
You could! [Laughs]
Agnes:
I think we do need it in all different sorts of ways. But interestingly, I
think we even need it in the explanation of behavior. So that, you know, I
tried to argue for that in my book—essentially what I say is, Here’s this
phenomenon, aspiration. And in order to apply it as an explanatory concept—to
say, Hey, this person was aspiring—you need to have reason to believe that the
thing that they’re aspiring towards is in fact good. So it’s an explanatory
concept that only applies in certain normative contexts. So you could think
that’s wrong but that’s like, that’s at least a possibility. Yes, go ahead.
Robin:
I’m planning at the moment to disagree with that, but you have the last word.
Agnes:
[Laughs] Okay! All right. Thanks.
Robin:
All right.